01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

22 <strong>Presuppositions</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Pronouns</strong><br />

Note, by contrast, that the presupposition that a group of girls is contextually<br />

given, which is triggered by the definite NP the girls, will go through no<br />

matter what.<br />

For good measure, here are some further examples that demonstrate how<br />

presuppositions <strong>and</strong> implicatures diverge:<br />

(43) Wilma hopes that }<br />

Wilma doubts that. .<br />

Wilma<br />

Can doubts<br />

tell that ·f<br />

if<br />

Fred kissed some of the girls. gIrlS.<br />

C you t e 11 me I<br />

Let's go <strong>and</strong> see if<br />

According to my intuitions, none of these sentences definitely imply that<br />

Fred didn't kiss all the girls, <strong>and</strong> at least some of them definitely don't imply<br />

this. By contrast, each of these sentences clearly implies, in the absence of<br />

evidence to the contrary, that there were girls. <strong>Presuppositions</strong> show<br />

projection behaviour; implicatures do nothing of the sort.<br />

If it cannot be shown that conversational implicatures are liable to escape<br />

from embedded positions, as presuppositions are, then a <strong>for</strong>tiori it cannot be<br />

shown that they are blocked or suspended under some circumstances. Cases<br />

like the following, <strong>for</strong> example, do not show that some implicatures exhibit<br />

projection behaviour:<br />

(44) a. The water is warm, <strong>and</strong> perhaps even hot.<br />

b. The water is warm. In fact, it is hot.<br />

c. The water is warm, if not hot.<br />

Horn (1989: 234-235) makes a distinction between implicature blockers <strong>and</strong><br />

implicature suspenders. In (44a) an implicature is blocked, according to<br />

Horn: in this case the speaker explicitly conveys that, <strong>for</strong> all he knows, the<br />

water may be hot, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e the implicature that the water is not hot,<br />

which would normally be licensed by the use of the scalar adjective warm, is<br />

blocked. In (44b) this implicature is suspended: the first sentence licenses the<br />

implicature, but it is removed by the second statement, which contradicts it.<br />

Finally, (44c) is ambiguous <strong>and</strong> may be construed as an instance either of<br />

suspension or blocking. In the <strong>for</strong>mer case, the speaker is taken to convey<br />

that he doesn't know if the water is hot; in the latter, his statement implies<br />

that the water is not hot.<br />

Judging from the way he describes what is going on in (44a-c), Horn must<br />

be assuming that the quantity implicature induced by warm exhibits<br />

projection behaviour. But it doesn't really. Consider (44b) first. Here the<br />

implicature is licensed by a simple sentence, only to be cancelled by the next<br />

statement. This could never happen to a presupposition. Compare (44b)<br />

with:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!