01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Presupposition 15<br />

b. If Barney took care of the manager, then it was Fred who shot<br />

the porter.<br />

(33) a. Someone shot the porter, <strong>and</strong> it was Fred who shot the porter.<br />

b. If someone shot the porter, then it was Fred who shot the<br />

porter.<br />

Each of these sentences contains a cleft sentence which triggers the<br />

presupposition that someone shot the porter, but while a speaker who<br />

uttered any of the sentences in (31) or (32) would be required to make this<br />

presupposition, he would not be taken to presuppose this if he uttered either<br />

of the sentences in (33). In the case of (33a) we would say that it had been<br />

asserted rather than presupposed that someone shot the porter, <strong>and</strong> (33b)<br />

doesn't imply in any way that the porter has been shot. Intuitively it is<br />

obvious why the presupposition is blocked in (33) but not in (31) or (32).<br />

Apparently, if the second half of a conjunction or conditional is of the <strong>for</strong>m<br />

CP{X}, j{x}, <strong>and</strong> X x is entailed by the first half, then the presupposition will be<br />

blocked; otherwise it will go through. So the following generalizations seem<br />

to hold: 7<br />

(34) a. 'CP{X} 'j{x} <strong>and</strong> ",' y' requires the presupposition that xX<br />

'cp '(j <strong>and</strong> y{x}' ",{X}' requires the presupposition that x, X, unless x X is<br />

entailed by cp j<br />

b. 'if CP{X} j{x} then ",' y' requires the presupposition that xX<br />

'if cp j then y{x}' ",{X}' requires the presupposition that X, x, unless X x is<br />

entailed by cp j<br />

Suppose now that it is suggested that these are not just empirical<br />

generalizations, but lexical rules: (34a) is part of the lexical meaning of <strong>and</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> (34b) is part of the lexical meaning of if. . ... . then. There are several<br />

problems with this suggestion. First, if we just postulate that (34a, b) are<br />

lexical rules, we don't have much of an explanation to boast of; we have<br />

merely codified our observations in the lexicon. Secondly, if we just say these<br />

generalizations are accounted <strong>for</strong> by lexical rules, <strong>and</strong> leave the matter at<br />

that, it is implied that these are purely conventional regularities, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

doesn't seem to right, since it is intuitively obvious that these generalizations<br />

hold <strong>for</strong> a reason. Thirdly, <strong>and</strong> this is what Stalnaker (1973, 1974) worries<br />

about, this proposal entails that the meanings of the connectives are much<br />

more complex than they ought to be, intuitively speaking. In particular, it<br />

7<br />

7 These are Karttunen's (1973a) initial filtering conditions <strong>for</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> if.. . ... then. Karttunen<br />

shows that these conditions are not quite adequate, <strong>and</strong> ends up proposing rather more<br />

sophisticated rules, but these fine points need not concern us here.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!