01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

182 <strong>Presuppositions</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Pronouns</strong><br />

utterance has a hypothetical common ground suggested by the immediately<br />

preceding context' (ibid.); <strong>and</strong> finally (iii) modal subordination may not<br />

make available to anaphoric expressions antecedents that have no explicit<br />

representation in the given DRS (1989: 705).<br />

Roberts's first constraint restricts modal subordination to utterances in<br />

non-factual mood. This constraint is needed to explain why the second it in<br />

(17) cannot link up to the indefinite a bear. bear:<br />

(17) Fred may have seen a bear^. i . It/s It-'s a big one.<br />

This example shows quite clearly that, without any further constraints, the<br />

notion of antecedent accommodation nullifies the restrictions that DRT<br />

imposes on anaphoric reference. Pending rather severe restrictions, any<br />

theory which adopts antecedent accommodation is a null theory of anaphora,<br />

which predicts that anything goes, <strong>and</strong> the constraints Roberts proposes are<br />

intended to regain the effect of DRT's accessibility restriction.<br />

The non-factuality constraint excludes the anaphoric link in (17) on the<br />

grounds that the second sentence is 'factual', which in this case correlates<br />

with the absence of an overt modal expression. However, Roberts's non-<br />

nonfactuality<br />

constraint is weaker than it might appear to be at first sight,<br />

because she does not want to restrict modal subordination to sentences that<br />

contain overt modal operators. For example, she doesn't want this constraint<br />

to frustrate her analysis of (10), <strong>and</strong> postulates accordingly that on<br />

'pragmatic grounds, we may assume that neither disjunct of a disjunction is<br />

asserted, <strong>and</strong> hence that both are nonfactual.' (1989: 702) It would seem,<br />

there<strong>for</strong>e, that this constraint is not nearly restrictive enough, because it<br />

allows modal subordination of any non-entailed clause, as in the following:<br />

(18) a. Gurnemanz may have bought a new swordi. Kundry thinks<br />

that iti is too heavy <strong>for</strong> him.<br />

b. Fred may have seen a bear^.. t<br />

Iti It; can dance.<br />

In these cases modal subordination does not seem to be possible. But as both<br />

examples obey the non-factuality constraint, Roberts's theory does not<br />

exclude this possibility. It would seem advisable, there<strong>for</strong>e, to strengthen this<br />

constraint by restricting modal subordination to sentences that contain overt<br />

modals, or that at least are interpreted as modals.<br />

Roberts's second constraint requires that accommodated material be<br />

'fresh' <strong>and</strong> hence must be copied from a recent portion of the discourse<br />

representation. It is this constraint, presumably, that applies to discourses<br />

like the following:<br />

(19) A thief might try to break in. So we should tell our neighbour that<br />

we're away <strong>for</strong> the weekend, <strong>and</strong> unchain the dog be<strong>for</strong>e we go out.<br />

If that doesn't scare him off, nothing will.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!