01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

60 <strong>Presuppositions</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Pronouns</strong><br />

These constraints act upon the interpretation process through the hearer's<br />

presumption that they will not be violated. Accordingly, the hearer tries to<br />

come up with an interpretation which violates as few of these constraints as<br />

possible. However, the Gricean constraints will sometimes pull in opposite<br />

directions. It may happen that the hearer must choose between an<br />

interpretation which violates the consistency constraint <strong>and</strong> another reading<br />

which violates the in<strong>for</strong>mativeness constraint. I will assume that, in such a<br />

situation, the consistency constraint takes priority over the in<strong>for</strong>mativeness<br />

constraint. This accords with the familiar observation that the quality<br />

maxim has a special status among the maxims: it is more urgent <strong>for</strong> a<br />

statement to be consistent than to be in<strong>for</strong>mative (cf. Grice 1981, Gazdar<br />

1979: 46-48).<br />

4~8).<br />

There are many respects in which the constraints in (44) regulate the<br />

interpretation of an utterance, <strong>and</strong> presupposition projection is just one of<br />

many processes affected. The principles of the binding theory interact with<br />

these constraints in different ways, some of which are more interesting than<br />

others. Let me begin with a less interesting case. In the following examples,<br />

there are conflicts between principle (A), which says that presuppositions<br />

must be project, <strong>and</strong> the consistency <strong>and</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mativeness constraints,<br />

respectively:<br />

(46) a. France is a republic. The King of France is bald.<br />

b. The King of France is bald. The King of France is bald.<br />

In (46a) the presupposition cannot be bound, obviously, <strong>and</strong> it cannot be<br />

accommodated without violating the consistency constraint. Similarly, the<br />

presupposition triggered by the second occurrence of the King of France in<br />

(46b) can neither be bound nor accommodated without violating the<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mativeness constraint. Intuitively, I should say that in both cases<br />

projection 'succeeds', <strong>and</strong> Gricean constraints are consequently violated, but<br />

I set no great store by intuitions about this sort of example (cf. § 1.6), <strong>and</strong><br />

hence<strong>for</strong>th I will assume <strong>for</strong> convenience that principle (A) of the binding<br />

theory is not defeasible.<br />

Things become more interesting when we consider principle (B), which<br />

says that binding is preferred to accommodation. The following example<br />

shows this principle to be defeasible by general constraints on interpretation:<br />

(47) Fred's wife will be at the reception, so Barney will be sorry that his<br />

wife can't come.<br />

Suppose the hearer doesn't know that Barney is married. In principle, the<br />

presupposition triggered by his wife may there<strong>for</strong>e be bound to the reference<br />

marker representing Fred's wife. But if the presupposition were so bound,<br />

the resulting interpretation would be inconsistent, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e an

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!