01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The satisfaction theory 109<br />

entertain several hypotheses about the common ground, some of which he<br />

may deem to be more plausible than others. An interesting consequence of<br />

this proposal is that it opens a new perspective on one of the problems that I<br />

discussed in the <strong>for</strong>egoing. I observed that it is difficult to see how % X can be<br />

more plausible than the weaker ~ i, X, as the argument from improbability<br />

requires, but Beaver would say that this difficulty only arises because I have<br />

been asking the wrong question. What I should have asked instead,<br />

according to Beaver, is whether the hearer finds it more likely that the<br />

common ground satisfies X / or just q> ~ %. X. And the hearer's answer to this<br />

question might very well be that the <strong>for</strong>mer possibility is more likely than the<br />

latter.<br />

Although Beaver's proposal offers a solution to one of the problems that<br />

have come up in the <strong>for</strong>egoing, I don't see that it improves matters in others<br />

than this respect. Beaver shows how the satisfaction theorist can consistently<br />

adopt the argument from improbability without having to give up on the<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard dynamic semantics of § 3.1. However, as I have pointed out in this<br />

section, it is clear that at least <strong>for</strong> conditionals this semantics is inadequate,<br />

<strong>and</strong> it still remains to be seen how a more sophisticated semantics of<br />

conditionals can be incorporated into the satisfaction framework. Secondly,<br />

Beaver's version of the improbability argument does nothing to alleviate the<br />

problems illustrated by (32)-(35). Indeed, it seems to me that if, instead of<br />

asking whether the (c) propositions are more plausible than the (b)<br />

propositions, we now ask which ones are more likely to be part of the<br />

common ground, it becomes even more questionable that there will be a<br />

majority vote <strong>for</strong> (c), as the argument from improbability requires. And<br />

finally, Beaver's version of the argument of improbability doesn't account <strong>for</strong><br />

the difference between, <strong>for</strong> example, (37a) <strong>and</strong> (37b).<br />

Summarizing the results of this section <strong>and</strong> the previous two, I have argued<br />

against the idea that the proviso problem can be solved along the lines first<br />

suggested by Karttunen <strong>and</strong> Peters. I have objected against the very idea of<br />

deriving the required inferences in two steps, <strong>and</strong> have criticized two<br />

arguments that have been proposed to account <strong>for</strong> the alleged strengthening<br />

of conditional presuppositions. My main conclusions are: that the<br />

conditional presuppositions which the satisfaction theory predicts are mere<br />

artefacts of that theory; that the notion that the observed inferences are to be<br />

derived in a two-step process is ill conceived; <strong>and</strong> that there is at present no<br />

account that explains how this strengthening might be accomplished.<br />

3.5 Further problems<br />

The main problem with the satisfaction theory is that certain of the presuppositions<br />

that it predicts are conditionalized whereas intuitively presup-<br />

they

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!