01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Names 219<br />

Since John treats anaphora as a special case of presupposition, he assumes<br />

that the pronoun triggers the presupposition that there is a given person who<br />

is female, <strong>and</strong> that it is asserted that this person is happy. There is no suitable<br />

antecedent <strong>for</strong> this presupposition to be bound to, so it must be accom-<br />

accommodated.<br />

But even so John will try to integrate the presupposition with his<br />

other knowledge, which is to say, in the present case, that he will connect it<br />

to his representation of Mary. Thus John's belief box, in which his representation<br />

of my commitment slate is embedded, may be pictured as follows:<br />

(26) [x: woman x, x is named 'Mary', x is in the kitchen,<br />

repre-<br />

Bart believes: [x: person x, female x, happy x]]<br />

(This representation abstracts away from the concerns that engaged us in<br />

Chapter 5.) John believes that there is a woman called Mary, that she is in<br />

the kitchen, <strong>and</strong> that I believe of this person that she is a female person who<br />

is happy. Or rather, the person that John's beliefs are about <strong>and</strong> the person<br />

that he takes my statement to be about are counterparts. This is why the<br />

pronoun in (24) appears to be rigid.<br />

By uttering (24) I have conveyed the in<strong>for</strong>mation in (25), part of which is<br />

that Mary is a female person; <strong>for</strong> this is the descriptive content of the<br />

pronoun she (by approximation, at least). But when we ask John if what I<br />

have said might be true even if it transpired that Mary is a man, his answer<br />

will be yes. This is a reasonable answer because one very common way of<br />

interpreting 'what is said' is by restricting it to asserted in<strong>for</strong>mation.<br />

If instead of (24) I had uttered (22), John would construe the name as<br />

'rigid' <strong>for</strong> the same reason he would construe the pronoun in (24) as 'rigid'.<br />

And he would say that the property of being named Mary is not part of what<br />

I have said <strong>for</strong> the same reason he would say that the property of being a<br />

female person is not part of the statement made by (24).<br />

7.5 Concluding remarks<br />

It is always possible to misconstrue a story, no matter how simple, <strong>and</strong> I know<br />

from experience that my story about names is especially liable to be<br />

misunderstood, so let me briefly mention some of the things I didn't claim<br />

<strong>and</strong> don't want to claim, either.<br />

First, I don't want to claim that names are pronouns. This is how Sommers<br />

(1982) puts it, but not I. I do want to claim that names are very much like<br />

pronouns. They both are presuppositional expressions, <strong>and</strong> have the full<br />

complement of possible interpretations that presuppositional expressions<br />

generally allow <strong>for</strong>. But, of course, the descriptive content of a pronoun is of<br />

a different category than that of a name, which makes it much easier to<br />

construct examples of 'blocking' <strong>for</strong> pronouns than <strong>for</strong> names. For example:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!