01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

84 <strong>Presuppositions</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Pronouns</strong><br />

sense, <strong>and</strong> those which do might be classified as anaphors in a derivative<br />

sense. But the same will hold true of semantically attenuate full NPs, like<br />

the thing or the animal.<br />

Given the right kind of context, even the poorest pronouns can be<br />

interpreted by way of accommodation (§ 2.4.3). But such cases are<br />

exceptional: pronouns <strong>and</strong> other semantically attenuate definites are<br />

generally anaphoric. Many definite NPs are not like this. Descriptions like<br />

the German president <strong>and</strong> the moon, to name only two examples, are specific<br />

enough not to be restricted <strong>for</strong> their reference to those entities which are in<br />

focus. It might be thought that at least some of these expressions are<br />

problematic <strong>for</strong> the binding theory. For it seems that the theory predicts that<br />

in a discourse in which the moon (or a moon) has not been mentioned yet,<br />

the definite NP the moon would have to be construed via accommodation.<br />

But this conclusion is unacceptable, <strong>for</strong> surely the moon will normally be<br />

used to refer to the moon. There is no deep problem here, however, <strong>for</strong> as we<br />

have already seen in § 2.4.3, the universe of a DRS need not be restricted to<br />

objects which have been introduced explicitly <strong>and</strong> by linguistic means. Since<br />

a DRS is a representation of the speaker's commitment slate, it is natural to<br />

assume that it may also contain in<strong>for</strong>mation which derives from other<br />

sources. Most speakers may be assumed to know that there is a moon, so we<br />

can maintain after all that, as a rule, the definite NP the moon is construed by<br />

way of binding rather than accommodation.<br />

Some presuppositions are easier to accommodate than others. While<br />

pronominal presuppositions are usually bound, the presuppositions<br />

triggered by certain factive verbs or definite NPs are quite readily<br />

accommodated. Van der S<strong>and</strong>t (1992) suggests that such differences<br />

correlate with the descriptive richness of presuppositions: pronouns are<br />

semantically attenuate expressions, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e must be bound, whereas<br />

the presuppositions triggered by factives may be quite specific, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e<br />

can be accommodated. This explanation is a plausible one, but it is<br />

incomplete. For instance, it seems that the presuppositions triggered by too<br />

may be as specific as factive presuppositions, but nonetheless the latter are<br />

easily accommodated, while the <strong>for</strong>mer are not. Compare:<br />

(87) a. Fred doesn't know that someone tried to steal his lawn mower, mower.<br />

b. Barney tried to steal Fred's lawn mower too.<br />

The factive in (87a) triggers the presupposition that someone tried to steal<br />

Fred's lawn mower. (87b) has almost the same presupposition; assuming that<br />

the focus is on Barney, the presupposition triggered is that someone other<br />

than Barney tried to steal Fred's lawn mower. This is, if anything, more<br />

specific, but nonetheless the first presupposition is easily accommodated,<br />

while the second one must be bound. Or compare:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!