01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Attitude reports 135<br />

believe, but not, or not necessarily, the other way round. It is evident that<br />

the regularity expressed by the i-principle has something to do with this<br />

asymmetry, although it remains to be seen what exactly is the nature of the<br />

connection.<br />

The problem with (1) <strong>and</strong> many other attitude ascriptions, is that they may<br />

reasonably be taken to corroborate both the i-principle <strong>and</strong> the e-principle.<br />

We would normally infer from an utterance of (1) that Louise has a niece <strong>and</strong><br />

that she believes that she has one -— or, to put it otherwise, presuppositions<br />

that are triggered in the scope of an attitude verb may give rise to a two-sided<br />

reading, which is internal as well as external. 1 Such two-sided readings do<br />

not always come about, of course. In a situation in which Louise doesn't<br />

know that she has a niece, but is nonetheless acquainted with her niece in<br />

some other way, a merely external reading of (1) would be called <strong>for</strong>; whereas<br />

in a context in which Louise mistakenly believes that she has a niece, a<br />

strictly internal reading would be achieved. But often a two-sided reading<br />

will be the most natural one.<br />

It may be argued that both the internal <strong>and</strong> the external halves of these<br />

two-sided interpretations are of a presuppositional nature. First, it is clear<br />

that both the inference that Louise has a niece <strong>and</strong> the inference that she<br />

believes that she has a niece can be traced back to the definite noun phrase<br />

her niece. Secondly, both inferences appear to display the projection<br />

behaviour that is the hallmark of presuppositions.<br />

(5) Maybe Louise doesn't believe that her niece lives in Leeds.<br />

Here (1) is embedded within the scope of a modal <strong>and</strong> a negation operator,<br />

<strong>and</strong> as one would expect on the basis of the e-principle, it follows from (5)<br />

that Louise has a niece, while the i-principle correctly predicts that an<br />

utterance of this sentence would normally imply that Louise believes that<br />

she has a niece.<br />

In the light of these observations, it may seem attractive to take the<br />

position that both the i-principle <strong>and</strong> the e-principle are correct. Things are<br />

not as simple as that, however. Suppose that we extend our DRS language in<br />

such a way that representations like the following are well <strong>for</strong>med:<br />

(6) [: Louise believes: [K: [x: x is Louise's niece, x lives in Leeds]]<br />

This is intended as a nearly completed representation of (1), in which only<br />

one presupposition remains to be dealt with, i.e. that Louise has a niece. The<br />

precise semantics of conditions of the <strong>for</strong>m 'u believes: 'If' xj/' will be left open<br />

1 Loar (1972) may have been the first one to observe two-sided readings, but his remarks are<br />

restricted to definite NPs. That other presupposition inducers can have such readings, too, was<br />

recognized, either implicitly or explicitly, by Fauconnier (1985), van der S<strong>and</strong>t (1988), Heim<br />

(1992), Kay (1992), <strong>and</strong> Zeevat (1992).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!