01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

178 <strong>Presuppositions</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Pronouns</strong><br />

breaks into the house <strong>and</strong> takes the silver, which is not what the second<br />

sentence in (6) means. Rather, this sentence seems to say something like:'// 'If<br />

a thief broke into the house, he would take the silver.'<br />

It is a familiar observation that the meaning of a modal expression is<br />

dependent on contextual factors. This context dependence is quite evident in<br />

examples like the following:<br />

(7) Your teeth might fall out.<br />

In this example it is perfectly clear what kind of contextual in<strong>for</strong>mation the<br />

sentence requires, at least intuitively speaking: (7) means something like 'If<br />

the circumstances were to be such <strong>and</strong> such, your teeth might fall out,' <strong>and</strong><br />

unless the context fixes what 'such <strong>and</strong> such' means, the sentence will be<br />

unintelligible. Consequently, it is difficult to imagine a conversation opening<br />

with an utterance of (7). If we put together this insight with the st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

construal of modals as quantifiers over possible worlds, we cannot but<br />

conclude that the quantificational domain of a modal expression is restricted<br />

by the context in which it occurs.1<br />

1<br />

This context dependence is Roberts's starting point. She observes that the<br />

second modal in (6) tends to be read as a conditional whose antecedent<br />

makes explicit the domain of the modal would. This is in con<strong>for</strong>mity with<br />

what we said in the preceding paragraph. What Roberts adds to this picture<br />

is a mechanism that actually fills in the modal domain with material furnished<br />

by the context. She calls this mechanism 'antecedent accommodation'.2 2 To<br />

illustrate the workings of this mechanism, let (8) be the initial representation<br />

of (6).<br />

(8) [: O[x: thief x, break-in x], [...:...] ] n-> ~ [z: take-silver z]]<br />

In this DRS the first sentence of (6) is represented as a simple possibility<br />

statement. This is not to say that this sentence is not relativized to a modal<br />

domain, but Roberts argues (1989: 698) that in this particular case the more<br />

orthodox representation is adequate enough, <strong>and</strong> I shall assume <strong>for</strong> the time<br />

being that she is right about this. The second sentence of (6) is represented<br />

initially by a conditional whose antecedent has not yet been specified. The<br />

connective 'O~' 'D->' is interpreted as a kind of conditional necessity, <strong>and</strong> its<br />

interpretation makes the antecedent accessible to the consequent, as does<br />

the ordinary DRT conditional. Now antecedent accommodation as<br />

presented by Roberts fills in the antecedent of such a conditional, generally<br />

by copying over in<strong>for</strong>mation from that part of the DRS which represents the<br />

immediately preceding discourse. In the example under discussion this<br />

1<br />

1 See Lewis (1979) <strong>and</strong> Kratzer (1981, 1991). The latter traces back the key observations to<br />

C.S. Peirce.<br />

2 In her 1996 article, Roberts presents this as an instance of local accommodation.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!