01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Presupposition 29<br />

actually has a number of cogent arguments <strong>for</strong> this theory, but I will spare<br />

you the details, because it will be evident already that it is not a good theory<br />

at all. To begin with, it is strange that someone should even consider<br />

developing such a theory in the first place. The evolution of fingers would be<br />

a plausible subject; the evolution of <strong>for</strong>efingers is obviously not. And to make<br />

things even worse, it turns out that there is no way this theory could be<br />

extended so as to deal with the evolution of the other fingers. In brief:<br />

without looking at the details we can tell be<strong>for</strong>eh<strong>and</strong> that the theory is ad<br />

hoc.<br />

Russell's theory of descriptions is like my niece's theory about <strong>for</strong>efingers.<br />

It confines its attention to a small portion of a broad class of related facts,<br />

<strong>and</strong> this limitation is essential to whatever plausibility it may seem to have. If<br />

my niece is convinced that her theory of <strong>for</strong>efingers is a sound one, it is only<br />

because she blithely ignores the other fingers. Similarly, one can only defend<br />

Russell's theory if he closes his eyes to the fact that definite NPs make up<br />

only a fraction of a large complex of related phenomena, which the theory<br />

cannot account <strong>for</strong>.<br />

Of course, Russellians are bound to deny that there are non-trivial<br />

similarities between definite NPs <strong>and</strong> factives, clefts, aspectual verbs, <strong>and</strong> so<br />

on. A thoroughbred Russellian will rather say something like this:<br />

A great range of disparate <strong>and</strong> unrelated phenomena has been<br />

dubbed 'presuppositional' over the years, but [...] it seems highly<br />

implausible that any theoretically important notion will do justice<br />

to the full range of data that semanticists professing an interest in<br />

'presupposition' seek to explain. (Neale 1990: 54)<br />

I have been at pains to show that there is wide range of empirical phenomena<br />

which cry out <strong>for</strong> a common explanation. This is what presupposition<br />

theorists call the projection problem. One can of course choose to ignore this<br />

problem or deny that it exists, as Neale does, but to do so is like saying that<br />

there is no theoretically important notion that can explain why fingers have<br />

evolved, because your niece has developed such a neat account of the<br />

evolution of <strong>for</strong>efingers.<br />

1.5 Where do they come from<br />

In the following chapters the focus will on the problem of presupposition<br />

projection, <strong>and</strong> it will be taken <strong>for</strong> granted that factive verbs presuppose<br />

their clausal complements, that a definite NP of the <strong>for</strong>m 'the N' triggers the<br />

presupposition that some N is contextually given, <strong>and</strong> so on. In short, it will<br />

be assumed that presuppositions are triggered by certain lexical items <strong>and</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!