01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

52 <strong>Presuppositions</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Pronouns</strong><br />

(31) a. [ 1 b x, z: z = x, Fred x, Fred z,<br />

bY: [ 2 y: rabbit y, x owns y] ::::}<br />

[3[ 3 ~: w: rabbit w, z owns w, w. pink w]]<br />

b. [ 1 b x: Fred x,<br />

b [ 2 y: rabbit y, x owns y] => ::::}<br />

[3~: [ 3 w: rabbit w, w. x owns w, w. pink w]]<br />

Finally, the last remaining presupposition, [w: rabbit w, x owns w], is bound<br />

in (31b 2 ), so that we end up with (32a), which is equivalent to (32b):<br />

(32) a. [x: Fred x,<br />

[y, w: w = y, rabbit y, x owns y, rabbit w, x owns w] => ::::}<br />

[: pink w]]<br />

b. [x: Fred x, [y: rabbit y, x owns y] ::::} => [: pink y]]<br />

This DRS adequately represents the preferred interpretation of (28a). In<br />

particular does it not follow from (32) that Fred has a rabbit, <strong>and</strong> thus it is<br />

correctly predicted that someone who utters (28a) does not thereby commit<br />

himself to the assumption that Fred has a rabbit. The presupposition which<br />

originates in the consequent of the conditional is bound in the antecedent,<br />

just as a personal pronoun might have been bound, <strong>and</strong> thus is 'blocked': the<br />

matrix sentence doesn't inherit the presupposition that Fred has a rabbit.<br />

(28b) contains three presupposition triggers (<strong>for</strong> pronouns are treated as<br />

ordinary presupposition-inducing expressions), <strong>and</strong> its initial representation<br />

is the following: 6<br />

(33) [: lli, [a, y: v: Fred u, rabbit v, v. u owns v, v. pink v] ::::} => [~: [w: male w, happy w]]<br />

Neither of the presuppositions triggered in the antecedent of (33) can be<br />

bound, <strong>and</strong> both will there<strong>for</strong>e have to be accommodated. As in the first<br />

example, there are two DRSs in which these presuppositions might be<br />

accommodated, <strong>and</strong> as be<strong>for</strong>e it is predicted that they will be accommodated<br />

in the principal DRS, which yields:<br />

(34) [u, v: Fred u, rabbit v, u owns v, [: pink v] ::::} => [~: [w: male w, happy w]]<br />

The remaining presupposition is (in fact, must be) bound at top level, <strong>and</strong><br />

thus the interpretation of (28b) results in (35a), which is equivalent to (35b):<br />

6<br />

6 In (33) the pronoun he is represented by the presupposition [w: male(w)], whereas in the<br />

<strong>for</strong>egoing it was assumed that the anaphor merely introduced a new reference marker. I consider<br />

the <strong>for</strong>mer representation to be the correct one, because pronouns generally have at least some<br />

descriptive content (but see Bosch, 1983: 151-157, <strong>for</strong> a discussion of what he calls 'pure', i.e.<br />

semantically empty, anaphors). However, I shall only use the official representation of pronouns<br />

when it helps to bring home some point or other -— in this case: that anaphoric pronouns are just<br />

like other presuppositional expressions.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!