01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Names 205<br />

why use this word when a possessive pronoun would have done just as well3<br />

3<br />

If this is correct, then we should be able to come up with better examples if<br />

we can somehow motivate the repetition of the name. And we can, <strong>for</strong><br />

instance by increasing the distance between the name <strong>and</strong> its antecedent<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or by introducing competing antecedents:<br />

(7) a. If a child is christened 'Bambi', <strong>and</strong> Disney Inc. hear about it,<br />

then they will sue Bambi's parents.<br />

b. The name of a product is essential to its commercial success.<br />

For example, if you want to buy washing powder <strong>and</strong> are given<br />

the choice between 'Black', 'White', <strong>and</strong> 'Drab', you will<br />

choose White, won't you<br />

It seems to me that (7a) is better than (6b), <strong>and</strong> as far as I can tell there is<br />

nothing wrong with (7b).<br />

The following examples are cases of binding, too, intuitively speaking:<br />

(8) a. Every time we do our Beatles act, [the guy who impersonates]<br />

Ringo gets drunk afterwards.<br />

b. Every time John goes to see a per<strong>for</strong>mance of Hamlet, he falls<br />

in love with [the actress who plays the part of] Ophelia.<br />

(9) a. Perhaps Mary has a son named 'John' <strong>and</strong> perhaps<br />

( 1 . ., .,. c<br />

\ her<br />

{<br />

, . Vis the thief.<br />

[<br />

John<br />

son}.<br />

John J<br />

IS t<br />

h<br />

e t<br />

h·<br />

Ie<br />

f<br />

.<br />

b. Mary is under the illusion that she has a son named 'John' <strong>and</strong><br />

u i_ i- 4.u * f her son 1 . ,, ... r<br />

she believes that {h~~~~n{ T , } > is the thief.<br />

[ John J<br />

In (8a, b) the definite NPs as well as the names can be interpreted non-<br />

nonreferentially.<br />

On this interpretation, Ringo is more or less equivalent with<br />

'whoever impersonates Ringo', <strong>and</strong> the same holds, mutatis mut<strong>and</strong>is, <strong>for</strong><br />

Ophelia. In (9a, b) there is a preference <strong>for</strong> a non-referential interpretation,<br />

<strong>and</strong> intuitively her son or John in the second conjunct is 'bound' in the first.<br />

3<br />

3 This is a familiar situation in the presupposition literature. It is widely held, <strong>for</strong> example, that<br />

in a sentence like the following the presupposition that there is a king of France, which is<br />

triggered by the definite NP in the consequent of the conditional, is somehow intercepted in the<br />

antecedent:<br />

If France has a king, then the king of France is bald.<br />

Of course, this sentence is slightly awkward, too, <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> the same reason: there is no apparent<br />

reason why a full definite should be used instead of a pronoun.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!