01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

212 <strong>Presuppositions</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Pronouns</strong><br />

• names can be construed non-literally; <strong>and</strong><br />

• names can be construed generically. genetically.<br />

I don't mean to suggest that I can account <strong>for</strong> definiteness restrictions, the<br />

distinction between referential <strong>and</strong> attributive readings, non-literal<br />

construals, <strong>and</strong> genericity. The point I want to make is merely that, given that<br />

definites are subject to definiteness restrictions <strong>and</strong> have referential,<br />

attributive, non-literal, <strong>and</strong> generic interpretations, the presuppositional<br />

theory of names leads us to expect that the same will hold <strong>for</strong> names, which<br />

it does.<br />

The remaining observations from § 7.1 require more detailed explanations:<br />

• Names are typically, though not always, used to refer to objects that are<br />

part of the common ground. That names prefer their referents to be given is<br />

a characteristic they have in common with all other presupposition inducers.<br />

We distinguished two ways of being part of the common ground: either the<br />

intended referent was already introduced into the discourse, or it is given in<br />

broader context in which the discourse takes place. To say that the<br />

presuppositions triggered by names are typically given in one of these ways<br />

is to say that they are rarely construed by means of accommodation. This is<br />

a peculiarity they share with many other presupposition inducing<br />

expressions, including some types of definite NPs; I will return to this point<br />

below.<br />

• Names have bound-variable uses. Any presupposition that is linked to an<br />

antecedent in an embedded DRS will seem to behave like an element bound<br />

by a quantifier. So this is just a special case of the general rule that<br />

presuppositions prefer to be linked to a given antecedent. 8<br />

(14) a. If a child is christened 'Bambi', then Disney will sue Bambi's<br />

parents. (= (6b))<br />

b. [: [x: child x, x is christened 'Bambi']<br />

~ => [y: [u: u is named 'Bambi', Disney sues u's parents]]<br />

c. [: [x: child x, x is christened 'Bambi', x is named 'Bambi']<br />

~ => [: Disney sues x's parents]]<br />

The second occurrence of the name Bambi in (14a) triggers the<br />

presupposition that there is someone named Bambi, as shown in (14b) (at its<br />

first occurrence the name is mentioned, not used). This presupposition is<br />

bound in the antecedent of the conditional, <strong>and</strong> the resulting interpretation<br />

8 Here I revert to the st<strong>and</strong>ard DRT analysis of conditionals, but only because it makes <strong>for</strong><br />

DRSs that are easier to parse than the ones I have proposed (§ 6.4).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!