14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

96<br />

A BSOLUTE( S ) SPIELEN<br />

Nonetheless, the sequence of confrontations, e.g. the antagonistic, game-like Spiel<br />

cannot go on forever without coming to a close, otherwise there would be no rationale and<br />

its meaning would have to be found outside of it (which means: outside of human history,<br />

outside of this world and this thought, in an otherworldly universe inaccessible to us). This<br />

may well be the case, but philosophy cannot accept an answer that would doom it to the<br />

irrelevance of a consolatory discipline (in the literal sense, also, of being forced to take up<br />

a disciplinary role: how, otherwise, could we control the madness springing forth from an<br />

incomprehensible, non-human world?) <strong>Philosophy</strong>’s raison d’être is that there must be a<br />

way to make sense—and express in concepts— the true way things are. This translates into<br />

the necessity of a closed system. The concept of Spiel used by Hegel captures the property<br />

of closure in its play-like side. Play is the paradigmatic self-enclosed activity that is totally<br />

bent upon itself and does not need to refer to its outside to be both valuable, meaningful,<br />

and rewarding.<br />

However, if closure is no doubt necessary, it is far from clear what this closure is about,<br />

or, more precisely, what it closes. It is necessary, for example, to transform work, the real<br />

work of the negative in effective history, into a game being played. It is only because the<br />

work, once performed, is recognized as the necessary part of a concluded and self-enclosed<br />

process that the process itself can be understood as a game. The necessity of closure dis-<br />

qualifies any “open,” pantragic solution to the problem of the absolute. Still, it does not<br />

necessarily follow that a closed system has to reduce Reason to Fate, as Habermas con-<br />

tends. To put it differently: closure, the circle of circles, etc., are just the names, the signa-<br />

tures, so to speak, of the Hegelian concept that unites, in my terms, the playful and the<br />

serious, the negative and the affirmative. The necessity that the system be closed reinforces<br />

and repeats the demand—a demand perhaps impossible to satisfy—that Hegel imposes on<br />

the concept. In itself, however, closure does not provide an answer. To uphold the necessi-<br />

ty—totally internal to Hegel’s thought— of a closure as the visible mark of his inevitable<br />

defeat and ultimate surrender to a pantheistic fatalism just misses the point. The issue is to<br />

understand what closure means, what it closes and what comes together in that closure. The<br />

issue is whether that closure is indeed possible, which means: whether Absolute Knowing

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!