14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

S PIELEN, THE ABYSS, AND THE CHILD<br />

mode of being of the child at play, his acting, is governed absolutely by the rules of the<br />

game that delimits the playspace: no transgression is possible, lest the game itself is dis-<br />

solved. But the “foundation” of the rules, their “ground” in the proper metaphysical sense<br />

of Grund is totally absent because the rules have been created by the player itself who is<br />

free to change them at will and anytime. Therefore, we must affirm that Spiel is constituted<br />

by rules whose value is absolute within the real of play (within the spatiotemporal leeway,<br />

the Zeit-Spielraum), but whose Grund is arbitrary. However, such a characterization is still<br />

insufficient insofar as it suggest a clear-cut division between the institution and the execu-<br />

tion of the rules. What is worse, such a characterization suggests a bipartite and essential<br />

static process in which an initial “legislative” phase is followed by successive and properly<br />

ludic executive stage. What is most essential in the ludic process—and I believe, in the on-<br />

tological context within which Heidegger talks— is precisely the absence of such a division<br />

which can be retraced only a posteriori. We might say that such a clear-cut division is valid<br />

only in abstracto and more precisely if we abstract from the time of play. Time exists, with-<br />

in the game, as the changing of the rule, as a creation of new rules that replace the old ones.<br />

The intrinsic compenetration of arbitrariness and rigor that is typical of play comports<br />

necessarily that the being of the player is always, and at the same time, inside and outside<br />

play, because it has to be inside the game being played as long as it is following the rules<br />

and outside of the played game and inside the playing game, as it were, insofar as it finds<br />

itself creating the rules that define a new playspace. The being of the player is the being at<br />

the limit, or, better, the being living on the limit, the being living on the ever renewing limit<br />

that divides the time of play when the player is totally absorbed within the Spielraum from<br />

the time when the Spielraum itself is defined. “It plays since it plays,” says Heidegger, and<br />

in the clause we should hear the intrinsic and essential duplicity of play that finds in itself<br />

its rigorous, and therefore arbitrary, law.<br />

It is this double movement, I believe, that thinking must appropriate in order to become<br />

a thinking of play. Or rather, it is the double movement that play must give to thinking so<br />

that the latter may become play’s thinking. Play’s thinking can only be the thinking of the<br />

limit, the thinking that positions itself on the limit of the articulation constituted by the des-<br />

115

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!