14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

T HE ANACLASTIC ILLUSION OF A TRANSCENDENTAL UNITY<br />

from without has declared their unmovable status, their “eternal truth.” Thus, Lévi-Strauss<br />

is right when he claims, at the end of the same passage quoted above, that the anthropolo-<br />

gist does not bring in from without the code of mythology, that he simply describes it from<br />

the inside—as he is allowed to do— by noticing its operational effects on the mythological<br />

sequences and themes. He is right inasmuch as he refers to the operationality of the rules<br />

discovered, to their mode of functioning, and to that alone. He is not allowed to make same<br />

claim, however, if he refers to the theoretical move that allows that operationality to be<br />

fixed in place (and time) once and for all. That, he would have brought in from without,<br />

because there is nothing inside the anaclastic structure that can grant such an unmovable<br />

role to any element playing inside it. In fact, in this second view of the structure, one sees<br />

that the center “does not have a natural location, that it is not a fixed place, but rather a func-<br />

tion, a kind of non-place where substitutions of signs are played ad infinitum.” Once the<br />

center of the structure—which, once again, is nothing less that its structurality, i.e. the prin-<br />

ciple or rule allowing the refractions and reflections of its constitutive elements—once the<br />

center has been so defined, it is easy to see that “a constant or invariant is defined less by<br />

its permanence and duration than by its function as a center, if only relative.” 44 This point<br />

has two important consequences: first, it entails that the structuralist approach does not<br />

need a fixed, immutable structure in order to work as such. The center may temporary with-<br />

out ceasing to be a center, if it continues to perform its function, e.g. if it continues to rule<br />

the transformations among the different elements. Second, and consequently, it means that<br />

there may be room for the development of a whole “dynamics” of structures, insofar as the<br />

shifts that allow the center to change place—or, in other terms, the decisions that allow the<br />

rules of the game to change —may not be totally free and unconstrained. To put it differ-<br />

ently: the recognition that the center is a pure function which can move in time and space,<br />

44. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Mille plateaux (Paris: Minuit, 1980); Engl. tr. A Thousand Plateaus<br />

(Minneapolis, Minnesota UP) 411, 95. A proper discussion of Deleuze and Guattari’s argument for this<br />

statement would unfortunately require a space we cannot afford here. But its relevance and importance<br />

to a proper understanding of Lévi-Strauss cannot be underestimated, especially because it goes<br />

through a discussion of music‘s evolution (the center of the structure being the diatonic center of harmonic<br />

attraction in the classic period) and it is precisely on the basis of a discussion of music that Lévi-<br />

Strauss tries to establish, especially in “Finale,” the “stability” and “truth” of the structural laws regulating<br />

myths‘ refractions.<br />

295

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!