14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

188<br />

C HESS, GAMES, AND FLIES<br />

occurring in social interactions like economic transactions and strategic confrontations be-<br />

tween social groups. Although he used insights from actual gaming practices—especially<br />

from games with less than perfect information, like poker—his work had little to do with<br />

psychology and individual cognitive capabilities. 12 It was instead a rather classical example<br />

of the applied mathematics he had been pursuing all his life: he used mathematical tech-<br />

niques to turn a potentially useful but imprecise concept into a powerful analytical tool.<br />

Chess, it turns out, presents a rather uninteresting case for classical game theory, since<br />

it rather easily proved that it admits of a solution. Rather, they play an important heuristic<br />

function, being one the favorite examples von Neumann and Morgenstern use to illustrate<br />

their definitions of games in general. Since these definitions will provide the framework<br />

for any conceptual understanding of chess in Artificial Intelligence and beyond, it is impor-<br />

tant to review them, although briefly.<br />

The basic concepts of game theory—game, play, move, strategy and solution— are de-<br />

fined by von Neumann and Morgenstern in a single page of their work. The concept of<br />

game is rather counterintuitive: they distinguish<br />

between the abstract concept of a game and the individual plays of that<br />

game. The game is simply the totality of the rules which describe it. Every<br />

particular instance at which the game is played—in a particular way—from<br />

beginning to end, is a play. (49, their italics.)<br />

11. The history of game theory is actually richer, and it includes, at least, the contributions by the French<br />

mathematicians Emile Borel in the 1920s and 1930s. Borel provided the first clear definition of pure<br />

and mixed strategies and proved the minimax theorem for some limiting cases. However, it is John<br />

(then Johann) von Neumann who proved the general form of the theorem in 1928, while still at Göttingen.Unfortunately,<br />

the historical literature on game theory is not that abundant. A detailed reconstruction<br />

of a immediate context preceding and following the publication of von Neumann and<br />

Morgestern’s major work in 1944 is provided by Robert J Leonard in “Creating a Context…,” 29-76.<br />

See also Émile Borel, “La théorie du jeu et les équations intégrales à noyau symétrique gauche,”<br />

Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences, 173 (1921) 1304-1308; “Sur les jeux où interviennent<br />

l’hasard et l’habilité des jouers,” Elements de la théorie des probabilités, (Paris: Librairie Scientifique,<br />

1924).<br />

1<strong>2.</strong> In fact, it has been argued that von Neumann and Morgenstern emphasis on strategy vs. Moves in Theory<br />

of Games, and their shift away from minimax interpretation was precisely an attempt to move away<br />

from the psychological dimension generating the “circularity of the ‘I think he thinks that I think’ logic<br />

of strategically interdependent situations”; Andrew Schotter, “Oskar Morgenstern’s Contribution to<br />

the Development of the Theory of Games,” Roy Weintraub (ed.), Toward a History…, 106.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!