14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

N ON-PHILOSOPHY<br />

does not build the figures, but retrieve those that exist already) all these do not know how<br />

to use their own crafts, but only know how to hunt and deliver their discoveries to the dia-<br />

lecticians so that the latter can use them...” 1 One of the most important consequences of<br />

such an interpretation concerns the scope of philosophical inquiry. Once it has been decided<br />

that philosophy aims at the truth of the world as such, it follows that it is almost impossible<br />

to delimit a clearly defined domain bounding the scope of the research. Hegel stresses, as<br />

we have seen, that both empirical and formal sciences, on the contrary, have defined do-<br />

mains within which they pursue their research. This is not meant to suggest that the char-<br />

acterization is originally Hegelian. Just the opposite: its spirit (and most of its letter) is<br />

clearly Aristotelian. Let us remember the opening sentences of Metaphysics, Γ: “There is a<br />

science that investigates being as being and the attributes which belong to it in virtue of its<br />

own nature. [...] None of the other sciences considers being as being in general but, after<br />

having delimited a portion of it, investigates the attributes of this part.” 2 Not only such a<br />

distinction goes back to the beginnings of philosophy, but it has also become entrenched in<br />

everyday language. The common use of the word “philosophy” (like in “Apple’s philoso-<br />

phy about the personal computer”) denotes precisely a very general view, an abstract view<br />

that guides practices. However, although the general conception is widely shared across the<br />

history of philosophy, it remains that the particular formulations can be significantly differ-<br />

ent and I prefer to refer my discussion, for the sake of concreteness and precision, to the<br />

specific formulation that it receives in the Hegelian text. Of course, the boundaries of the<br />

domains in questions may be more or less clearly defined—often, it is only when a science<br />

has reached a certain theoretical maturity that its object can be fully specified, since the def-<br />

inition of the domain itself is a relevant part of the scientific effort.<br />

In the Lectures on the History of <strong>Philosophy</strong>, Hegel exploits this distinction between<br />

“empirical sciences” and philosophy to point out that the former can afford (which doesn’t<br />

mean that they always do, nor that they have to) the luxury to proceed by a progressive ac-<br />

1. See Plato, Euthydemos (282d,290c-d) in Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns, eds., The collected<br />

dialogues of Plato (New York: Pantheon Books, 1961), 396, 404. At this level of generality, philosophy<br />

has not changed much from Plato to Hegel.<br />

<strong>2.</strong> Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Γ 1003, 21-25<br />

127

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!