14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

46<br />

T HE END OF PHILOSOPHY<br />

the paradox—e.g. the possibility of philosophy. The Hegelian solution, instead, is to rein-<br />

terpret the antinomy by substituting a different reading of contradiction fro the classical<br />

one—e.g. by introducing dialectics. 14<br />

More generally, Hegel shows that if the notions of truth and history are taken seriously,<br />

then the very, undeniable fact that philosophy, e.g. the search for truth, might have a history<br />

brings about a paradox that casts a spell on philosophy itself and threatens to destroy its<br />

very possibility. This paradox, it may be worth remembering, arises when the implicit and<br />

deeply a-historical relationship of philosophy with its end is brought to the fore. The first<br />

conclusion to be drawn from it, then, is that unless philosophy takes an explicit stance to-<br />

wards its end, it can never exist, since it bounces from a series of historical temporal opin-<br />

ions to an a-historical truth that mutually converts into one another.<br />

But Hegel’s point can also be read from the conclusion to the premises, or, as the logi-<br />

cians say, by contraposition. Since it is a fact, contrary to the previous alleged conclusion,<br />

that philosophy has existed and does exist (and Hegel would be the last one to contest such<br />

a fact) it follows that it has, always, and more or less explicitly, taken a stance towards its<br />

end. In fact, we might say that what Hegel’s paradox does is to show how philosophy—<br />

Hegel’s philosophy first and foremost, and ours as well insofar as it might share some of<br />

Hegel’s assumptions on truth and history that bear the weight of the paradox—is tied to its<br />

ends. We might even say—but it would be too strong, since such a privilege is shared by<br />

other words—that what the paradox shows is that ‘end’ is the philosophical word par ex-<br />

cellence, since it is impossible to speak about or do philosophy without being drawn into<br />

thinking about the end and the ends, of philosophy and of philosophers. (Anyone existen-<br />

tially minded might want to push this thought a bit further and claim that philosophy, in the<br />

end, has just one concern: the end with a capital E, i.e. “the most extreme possibility”<br />

14. Removing the possibility of self-referential sentences is the classical, Russellian solution to the Liar<br />

paradox as it arises in set-theory. Although other non-Russellian alternatives are in fact possible, the<br />

difference between a logical “dis-solution” and the Hegelian “re-solution” of the antinomy remains unchanged,<br />

insofar as it involves a deeply different treatment of contradiction and a different concept of<br />

“solution.” For a detailed discussion of the Liar paradox see Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy, The<br />

Liar (Oxford: Oxford UP, 1987) and, more recently, Jon Barwise and Lawrence Moss, Vicious Circles<br />

(Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications, 1996), p. 177-197.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!