14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

288<br />

A NACLASTIC SUPPLEMENTS<br />

tute an ultimate sense, nor can it propose a [privileged] level of reference that would con-<br />

stitute a level of truth.” On the contrary, the only kind of “interpretation” that a mythologist<br />

can provide is to evidentiate the pertinent traits within a group of myths, their transforma-<br />

tions, etc., and “thereby to understand how a group of myths constitutes the representation<br />

of given world and strives to provide answers to some questions, not as statements, but in<br />

the very play of those representations.” 41 The “privileged level” sought by the philosopher<br />

survives, we might add, but it is not is not a level at all, and certainly not a level of reference<br />

to be found outside the structure: rather it is the play itself of the elements within the struc-<br />

ture. The “truth,” if there is any room left for this term, is the truth of the structure as seen<br />

from the inside, in the rearrangements of the various places that the terms can occupy.<br />

Therefore, two strictly related questions are left unanswered, at this stage of the anal-<br />

ysis, by Lévi-Strauss: (a) what is the reality of the structure whose play commands a group<br />

of (transformations of) myths and (b) what is the status of the truth about that very structure<br />

that is being discovered, about its play, when it is discovered by the anthropologist who is<br />

necessarily positioned outside it?<br />

However, the existence of these problems, and even their formulation in rather classi-<br />

cal terms we have just given, does not entail that the solution to the problem must be found<br />

within the confines of philosophy strictu sensu. The philosophical solutions we have<br />

sketched above with reference to Kant and Hegel, and most especially the use of the con-<br />

cepts of subject and object, might not be adequate for Lévi-Strauss’s structural analysis. In-<br />

deed, we should rather expect the opposite to be true, if the structuralist project is to be<br />

consistent with its professed goal of bringing philosophy to an end. In other words, it might<br />

be the case that the effort to unfold the implication of the structural method, still to a large<br />

extent absent in the work of the early 1960s (e.g. before Le cru et le cuit) will bring about<br />

a rethinking, a non-philosophical rethinking of those capital philosophical categories as<br />

subject and object. At any rate, the questions raised by the philosophers, and the impossi-<br />

bility to fit Lévi-Strauss’ model within either a Kantian or Hegelian model, brings up a<br />

problem whose solution is crucial to Structuralism, a problem that may be summed up in a<br />

41. Marcel Hénaff, Claude Lévi-Strauss…, 197.My emphasis.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!