14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

114<br />

A BSOLUTE( S ) SPIELEN<br />

sequence, the Geschick of being could be interpreted as the specific realization of a game<br />

instituted by someone else. On the contrary, they say “Aion/Geschick: a child that plays.”<br />

There are no psychological or mythological undertones in this accent on the ludic world of<br />

the child. The reference to such a world highlights a precise, and, supposedly, extremely<br />

relevant, feature of play by pointing to the relevance of child’s play. What is important<br />

about the way children play? Simply put, child’s play is creative. Creativity, here, means<br />

just that the child at play is capable, contrary to most adults, to invent the game while it<br />

plays. Child’s play is creative because it comports—in the same event—the institution as<br />

well as the execution of the act of playing. The child invents the rules of the game and, by<br />

so doing, creates a leeway which is not of course, spatial at all, but represents the spatiotem-<br />

poral field within which actions are possible. It is precisely this aspect, I believe, that<br />

Heidegger wants to emphasize by recalling the Heraclitean fragment and by underlining his<br />

reference to the world of the child. But there is more in that reference. In particular, there<br />

is another aspect of child’s play that Heidegger brings to the front in the lines immediately<br />

following the previous quotation. He says:<br />

Why does it play, the great child of the world-play Heraclitus brought into<br />

view in the Aion? It plays because it plays. The because withers away in the<br />

play. The play is without a “why”. It plays since (weil) it plays. [ib.]<br />

Play, as I have stressed in the previous pages, has no external finality, it is perfectly self-<br />

contained. Or rather: play resists the application of the very concept of finality, it resists the<br />

application of the concept of a final cause that finds it raison d’être outside play itself. Does<br />

this mean that play is totally arbitrary? Does this mean that the distinctive mark of any ludic<br />

phenomenon is its improvised, poetic, extemporaneous character, as Nietzsche once em-<br />

phasized? 21 The situation is actually more complex. Play, and especially child’s play, is nei-<br />

ther arbitrary nor rigorous, but both at the same time.<br />

“Play is without a why,” Heidegger affirms, and “it plays since it plays (es spielt weil<br />

es spielt).” This does not mean that play is completely arbitrary, but rather that the mode of<br />

being of play refers only to itself and only from and in itself is its rigor to be found. The<br />

21. Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Harmondsworth, Engl.: Penguin Books, 1978) 25.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!