14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

50<br />

T HE END OF PHILOSOPHY<br />

dition. However, Wissenschaft is not, by and large, qualitatively different from the current<br />

English word “science,” the main difference being one of scope, at least if one allows that<br />

different disciplines may have different methods to ascertain the objective validity of their<br />

truths. Far from being tainted by an old-fashioned conception of science, Wissenschaft is<br />

instead more general in scope and more epistemologically neutral than the current use of<br />

the term “science,” because it does not assume a built-in preference for the mathematical-<br />

physical paradigm as the standard of validity. When Hegel asserts that philosophy has to<br />

become a “science,” then, he is stating that the truths provided by philosophy must be as<br />

epistemologically valid as those provided by, say, physics or philology, but he is not assum-<br />

ing that there must me one preferred epistemological standard provided by a specific dis-<br />

cipline. To put it differently, there are no substantive claims hidden behind the use of the<br />

term Wissenschaft (which was in fact quite common at the time), but rather the effort to use<br />

a term broad enough to cover disciplines across the board with no special epistemological<br />

preferences. The use of the term Wissenschaft makes in fact Hegel closer to philosophers<br />

like Carnap and Russell than to what we ordinarily design with the umbrella term “Conti-<br />

nental” philosophy. The difference lies in the kind of truths (and therefore the kind of meth-<br />

ods) that philosophy can reach. There is little doubt that the Russellian analysis of<br />

propositions is far different from Hegel’s dialectical progression of concepts in the Wissen-<br />

schaft der Logik, but the epistemological goal that philosophy must attain is the same. 17<br />

It might be contended, however, that it is precisely this overvaluation of theory that<br />

makes Hegel’s argument for the end of philosophy suspicious. It might be said, in other<br />

words, that philosophy is, and perhaps has always been, engaged in the search for “Sophia”,<br />

the latter term to be reinterpreted as a form of practical wisdom and not as a science-like<br />

form of knowledge. The issue becomes whether such a (very broadly construed) “ethical”<br />

wisdom can stand on its own without a metaphysics to support it. As a matter of fact, in our<br />

17. More precisely, it may be said that it was as a reaction against the “metaphysics way of attaining truth”<br />

that the logical analysis was devised (see, for example, Carnap’s violent critique of Heidegger’s inaugural<br />

lecture on “What is metaphysics?” as a mere word-play that is meaningless because it just confounds<br />

the various meanings of “nicht.”). In other words: the path had to change so that the destination<br />

could be reached.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!