14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

G AMES AND STRUCTURES<br />

same functions, as in successive card games one periodically shuffles, cuts<br />

deals, plays, and takes the tricks. In other words, one repeats the same rules<br />

in spite of different deals. 2<br />

Lévi-Strauss goes as far as to quote von Neumann and Morgenstern’s work, and he of-<br />

ten presents the theory of games as the ideal language for a possible future science of com-<br />

munication that will unify sociology, economics and linguistics, e.g. the three disciplines<br />

that deal with the issue of the exchange (respectively, of women, goods, and messages)<br />

among human beings. He seldom ventures, though, into a discussion of the basic concepts<br />

of game-theories, limiting himself to present it as a tool that will prove indispensable. One<br />

of the few specific remarks concerns the different goals of parlor games and kinship sys-<br />

tems:<br />

The former are constructed in such a way as to permit each player to extract<br />

from statistical regularities maximal differential values, while marriage<br />

rules, acting in the opposite direction, aim at establishing statistical<br />

regularities in spite of the differential values existing between individuals<br />

and generations. In this sense they constitute a special kind of “upturned<br />

game.” 3<br />

As he immediately adds, however, such a difference does not mean that “societal” games<br />

cannot be treated with the same (game-theoretical) methods. Yet, we are not given further<br />

details on this point, and we have seen above that a precise characterization of the basic<br />

concept of game, strategy, move, etc., is crucial for a proper understanding of game theory.<br />

Edouard Delruelle is the author of one of the few studies on Lévi-Strauss’s work to pay at-<br />

<strong>2.</strong> Claude Lévi-Strauss, Anthropologie Structurale Deux (Paris: Plon, 1973) 149. Engl. tr. Structural Anthropology,<br />

volume 2 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976) 124, Lévi-Strauss’s emphasis. The<br />

essay was first published in 1960.<br />

3. Claude Lévi-Strauss, Anthropologie Structurale (Paris: Plon, 1958) 329; Engl. Tr. Structural Anthropology,<br />

(New York: Basic Books, 1963) 298. Lévi-Strauss actual formulation is a bit different, and in<br />

fact more strongly put, than the English translation: ”On pourrait dire que les secondes constituent des<br />

«jeux à l’envers,» ce que ne les empèche pas d’être justiciables des mêmes méthodes.” The same point<br />

about the specificity of “anthropological games” is repeated, in the context of the distinction between<br />

“games” and rites,” in the first chapter of La Pensée Sauvage. See also the “ouverture” of Histoire de<br />

Lynx, which opens the book on a chessboard theme, and the discussion of such a narrative move provided<br />

in the preface: Claude Lévi-Strauss, La pensée savage …Engl. tr. 30-33; Histoire de Lynx (Paris:<br />

Plon, 1991), 20-22 and 9-13; Engl tr. The Story of Lynx (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1995).<br />

213

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!