14.11.2012 Views

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

2. Philosophy - Stefano Franchi

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

H EGEL’ S PARADOX<br />

for better or for worse, by a different one. 12 But a history, in this sense, of past philosophies<br />

seems to make little sense, since, once again, on the one hand it would have to grant validity<br />

to different, successive philosophies, and on the other it would allow one truth to suppress<br />

another. A superseded truth is not very different from a mistake, being what has been rec-<br />

ognized as such. Furthermore, such a narration would be totally irrelevant to philosophy<br />

and philosophizing, given the necessity to start ex-novo every time.<br />

Conversely, if philosophy has a history then it cannot be a science, i.e. it cannot be phi-<br />

losophy, since there would have been truths objectively valid in the past. But again, multi-<br />

ple truths do not add up to a greater truth but constitute rather a series of opinions. Unless,<br />

of course, one is willing to abandon philosophy’s aspiration to be a science and set a more<br />

modest goal for it: to provide a general world-view compatible with the time in which it is<br />

developed. 13<br />

We face a classic dilemma, a proposition that opens up to two incompatible and equal-<br />

ly unsatisfactory consequences. Before we begin to explore it in further details, we may<br />

start by appreciating its real scope. It would be easy to dismiss the contradiction by relegat-<br />

ing it to the characteristic quagmires of a discipline, history of philosophy, which can serve<br />

useful purposes but is nevertheless distinct from philosophy proper. Easy—but wrong. The<br />

issue Hegel is trying to bring forth by pointing at the problematic relation between philos-<br />

ophy and its own history does not concern primarily historians—rather, it concerns philos-<br />

ophy itself (although it is well known that his solution of the problem will radically<br />

undermine the very possibility of such a distinction between theory and history). Hegel’s<br />

1<strong>2.</strong> There is another possibility I am not exploring here: namely, that philosophy’s history be envisioned<br />

as a continuous progress toward richer and richer theories. We are all familiar with this model of monotonic<br />

growth, since it corresponds to the received view about science’s progress. Hegel deals with it<br />

explicitly in the Lectures and I will discuss his position at length in section 4 below.<br />

13. In fact Husserl, in his polemic against Dilthey, traces back to Hegel the origin of such a view of philosophy.<br />

Husserl acknowledges that Hegel’s philosophy rejects such a view, but he claims that Hegel’s<br />

strong conception of history allows such a possibility, once the concept of absolute Wissen is relinquished:<br />

“Hegelian philosophy produced lasting effects by its doctrine on the relative justification of<br />

every philosophy by its own time—a doctrine, it is true, which in Hegel’s system, pretending to absolute<br />

validity, had an entirely different sense from the historistic one attributed to him by those generations<br />

which had lost, along with their belief in Hegelian philosophy, any belief whatsoever in absolute<br />

philosophy.” See Edmund Husserl, “<strong>Philosophy</strong> as a Strict Science…,” 229-30.<br />

39

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!