25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Quine</strong> on Reference and Ontology 117<br />

scientific questions, they are answered in terms of the effects that the<br />

world has on us and of our responses to those effects. Various forms<br />

of energy, most obviously light, sound, and heat, impinge on the<br />

surfaces of our body; in some cases, a person responds differentially to<br />

such impingements. Thus we may respond in one way when a certain<br />

pattern of light is impinging on our eyes and in another way when<br />

it is not. The body contains sensory surfaces that are stimulated<br />

by impingement of the relevant forms of energy; these stimulations<br />

affect behavior.<br />

It is a long way from forms of energy impinging on the body to our<br />

discourse and our thought being about the world. We need to see,<br />

in broad outline, how <strong>Quine</strong> thinks we get from one to the other.<br />

This discussion will take us, for a couple of pages, completely away<br />

from the subject of reference; this fact, that we can discuss <strong>Quine</strong>’s<br />

views on this subject without talking about reference, is of great<br />

significance.<br />

Our present concern, then, is <strong>Quine</strong>’s account of the transition<br />

from the impingement of energy on our sensory surfaces to the empirical<br />

content of our theories. The key here is <strong>Quine</strong>’s notion of an<br />

observation sentence. An observation sentence satisfies three conditions.<br />

First, it is a complete utterance whose truth-value varies<br />

with the occasion of utterance (‘There’s milk in the glass’ rather<br />

than ‘Milk is good for young children’). Second, for each individual,<br />

it is directly tied to stimulation of the sensory surfaces: The individual’s<br />

willingness to make the utterance, or to agree with it when<br />

another makes it, depends only on which of that individual’s sensory<br />

surfaces are being stimulated at that time. Third, from the point of<br />

view of the community of language speakers, the observation sentences<br />

are utterances about which there will be general agreement<br />

in any given circumstances. If I am in a situation that stimulates<br />

my sensory surfaces in such a way as to lead me to agree or disagree<br />

with a particular observation sentence, then any other speaker of the<br />

same language in the same situation would have his or her sensory<br />

surfaces stimulated in a way that results in the same verdict. <strong>Quine</strong><br />

speaks of “projecting ourselves into the witness’s position” (PTb 43;<br />

there is some vagueness in this idea, as <strong>Quine</strong> himself points out).<br />

Observation sentences will thus be uncontroversial, to the point<br />

of banality. ‘It’s raining’, ‘It’s red’ (or just ‘Red’), and ‘There’s a horse’<br />

might count as examples. Not by chance, these are the sorts of<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!