25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Quine</strong> on the Intelligibility and Relevance of Analyticity 53<br />

these: What claims need no justification at all? What inferences need<br />

no further justification? What inference preserves the degree of justification<br />

of any set of premises? <strong>Quine</strong> does eventually begin to<br />

address such questions, though in a less overtly epistemic and normative<br />

form. He does not do so, however, either in “Two Dogmas”<br />

or in the second chapter of Word and Object, which deals with translation<br />

and meaning.<br />

Insofar as <strong>Quine</strong>’s survey of ways to clarify concepts of meaning<br />

includes those attempts that would have been most naturally offered<br />

(and I think that, with the caveat of the previous paragraph, it does<br />

so) and insofar as the attempts fail (and they do), <strong>Quine</strong> can claim to<br />

have the basis of an inductive argument that the requisite behavioral<br />

criteria will not be forthcoming. So <strong>Quine</strong> does have an argument<br />

against the intelligibility of analyticity. It was never intended to be<br />

airtight. But its structure is fairly clear, its basis is a reasonable and<br />

minimal demand for behavioral criteria, and what it would take to<br />

defeat the argument is also clear. This is just what one would want<br />

from an argument in science.<br />

2. relevance<br />

I shall postpone the question of whether <strong>Quine</strong>’s challenge to provide<br />

behavioral criteria for analyticity can be met and shall turn instead to<br />

the so-called second dogma of empiricism. The opening paragraph of<br />

“Two Dogmas” identifies the second dogma as reductionism, and §5,<br />

where the second dogma is discussed, links it to the verification theory<br />

of meaning. This challenge to reductionism and the verification<br />

theory is slightly unexpected because, while both terms have many<br />

senses, <strong>Quine</strong> is in some sense both a reductionist and a verificationist.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> generally favors whatever reductions can be achieved,<br />

whether in ontology or in ideology, and the whole demand for behavioral<br />

criteria has its roots in verificationist accounts of significance.<br />

In any case, <strong>Quine</strong>’s motivation for taking them up here is that the<br />

verification theory (of meaning rather than significance) purports to<br />

be an account of synonymy. If it is acceptable in this capacity, then<br />

analyticity can be saved after all. So analyticity is still the topic. Indeed,<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> says that the two dogmas are at root identical (see TDEa<br />

38). Even so, something has profoundly changed in <strong>Quine</strong>’s discussion<br />

in §§5–6 beyond his consideration of a subsidiary thesis about<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!