25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Quine</strong> on the Intelligibility and Relevance of Analyticity 49<br />

But all demands for further clarification, if pushed far enough, have<br />

nowhere to turn but to terms earlier in the series; the complaint of<br />

circularity could be lodged everywhere. So <strong>Quine</strong>’s worry must lie,<br />

not with circularity, but with some defect of each of the terms in this<br />

sequence. <strong>Quine</strong> does not say so explicitly here, but his basic demand<br />

is for behavioral criteria. 1 This is a demand about which we need to<br />

ask several questions: What precisely is the demand? Is it legitimate,<br />

and if so, to what extent? What would be required to satisfy the legitimate<br />

portion of the demand? And can this be done? <strong>Quine</strong>’s demand<br />

for behavioral criteria is best understood as an instance of the many<br />

empiricist criteria of significance. Empiricists in the Viennese tradition<br />

had long sought to rule out metaphysics. Their strategy was to<br />

presume an observational basis and require some connection (in the<br />

form of observational criteria, correspondence rules, and the like)<br />

between that observational basis and the claims in question. Claims<br />

lacking the appropriate connection were said to be without empirical<br />

content. This is just what <strong>Quine</strong> says about the division of truths into<br />

the analytic and synthetic: it lacks empirical content and is, hence,<br />

a metaphysical article of faith. Since his favored observational basis<br />

is observable behavior, this is certainly methodological behaviorism,<br />

but by itself it need not rule out theoretical episodes of a fully mental<br />

sort. <strong>Quine</strong> does not spell out in any great detail what sort of connection<br />

he would approve between behavior and admissible concepts.<br />

Given the parallel with the demands of Carnap, however, we are left<br />

to surmise that the tie would permit theoretical concepts that are<br />

not fully expressible in the observational/behavioral framework.<br />

There is an irony in all this, besides the obvious one that <strong>Quine</strong> is<br />

pushing against Carnap the very demands that Carnap had pushed<br />

against the metaphysicians. This second irony is that many philosophers<br />

such as Hempel came to reject analyticity because they<br />

thought it could not meet <strong>Quine</strong>’s demands and at the very same time<br />

came to reject the whole idea of empiricist criteria of significance. 2<br />

On this issue, however, <strong>Quine</strong> never wavered. Carnap’s demand for<br />

empirical significance is among the features of Carnap’s philosophy<br />

that <strong>Quine</strong> most enthusiastically and enduringly approves.<br />

But is <strong>Quine</strong>’s demand legitimate, however much it may be modeled<br />

on Carnap’s? <strong>Quine</strong> thinks that it is because he thinks that the<br />

theory of language must be an empirical theory. Putting the matter<br />

this way, though, begs the question against Carnap. Carnap would<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!