25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Quine</strong> on Reference and Ontology 127<br />

saw, in barest outline, how such an explanation might go, at least for<br />

the simplest kind of sentences. It is very hard to see how any naturalistic<br />

explanation – an explanation along causal-scientific lines –<br />

could make an appeal to properties, entities that are, supposedly, not<br />

in space and time and not capable of causally interacting with us. 15<br />

There is, of course, room for other sorts of questions to be raised<br />

about <strong>Quine</strong>’s criterion of ontological commitment. The two we<br />

have discussed, however, at least indicate what that doctrine comes<br />

to and why <strong>Quine</strong> holds it. One immediate consequence of the doctrine<br />

is that talk of the ontological commitment of any body of informal<br />

theory draws on the idea of a regimentation of that body<br />

of theory, that is, a reformulation of it, actual or envisaged, into<br />

the language of first-order logic. This does not mean that we cannot<br />

talk about, say, the ontological commitments of Aristotelian physics:<br />

With some intellectual imagination and sympathy, we can consider<br />

what reformulation Aristotle himself might have accepted for his<br />

view if he had had first-order logic at his disposal. It does, however,<br />

mean that an author who rejects the idea of such a reformulation<br />

entirely is simply refusing to answer the ontological question as we<br />

understand it (or as <strong>Quine</strong> thinks we do, or should). Of course, we<br />

can imagine what a reformulation might look like, in spite of the objections<br />

of the author, but the imagined author himself is, on <strong>Quine</strong>’s<br />

view of the matter, simply rejecting the question.<br />

Another consequence of adopting <strong>Quine</strong>’s criterion is, of course,<br />

that the ontological commitments of any body of discourse are dependent<br />

on the way in which it is regimented (i.e., cast into the notation<br />

of first-order logic). Informal discourse, taken as such, has no<br />

definite ontology implicit in it, for there are various ways in which<br />

it can be regimented. Let us see what <strong>Quine</strong> says on this matter 16 :<br />

The common man’s ontology...isvague in its scope; we cannot tell in general<br />

which...things to ascribe to a man’s ontology at all, which things to<br />

count him as assuming. Should we regard grammar as decisive? Does every<br />

noun demand some array of denotata? Surely not: the nominalizing of verbs<br />

is often a mere stylistic variation. But where can we draw the line?<br />

It is a wrong question; there is no line to draw. Bodies are assumed....<br />

Beyond them there is a succession of dwindling analogies.<br />

. . . [A] fenced ontology is just not implicit in ordinary language. The idea<br />

of a boundary between being and nonbeing is a philosophical idea, an idea of<br />

technical science in a broad sense....Ontological concern is not a correction<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!