25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

22 robert j. fogelin<br />

becomes useless, and can give rise to no inference or conclusion. It is impossible,<br />

therefore, that any arguments from experience can prove this resemblance<br />

of the past to the future; since all these arguments are founded<br />

on the supposition of that resemblance. 1<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> both notes Hume’s despair at solving the problem of induction<br />

and clearly endorses it: “On the doctrinal side, I do not see that<br />

we are farther along today than where Hume left us. The Humean<br />

predicament is the human predicament” (EN 72).<br />

This commitment to Humean skepticism with regard to induction<br />

is, I believe, a fundamental aspect of <strong>Quine</strong>’s position. Moreover, it is<br />

more than bare acknowledgment of a puzzle that he finds impossible<br />

to solve. Not only does <strong>Quine</strong> accept Hume’s skeptical argument, his<br />

response to it – his way of dealing with it – is strikingly Humean as<br />

well. This important connection is evident in <strong>Quine</strong>’s notes for lectures<br />

he gave in 1946 on the history of philosophy. Michael Pakaluk<br />

was given access to these notes and published selections from them,<br />

with commentary, in a fine piece entitled “<strong>Quine</strong>’s 1946 Lectures on<br />

Hume.” These notes show that <strong>Quine</strong> had a subtle (and to my mind<br />

correct) understanding of the role that inductive skepticism played<br />

in Hume’s own attempt to naturalize philosophy, or as Hume described<br />

his project in the subtitle to the Treatise of Human Nature,<br />

his Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning<br />

into Moral Subjects.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> saw, for example, that Hume’s skepticism concerning induction<br />

was independent of Hume’s specific account of experience.<br />

Pakaluk remarks that “<strong>Quine</strong> is of course in great sympathy with<br />

Hume’s conclusion that there can be no justification for our inductive<br />

practices.” In fact, the passage he cites to support this says more:<br />

“Hume’s negative doctrine is inevitable, I think, in any thoroughgoing<br />

empiricism; and it does not depend on the extreme or questionable<br />

feature of his particular underlying system of elements and<br />

psychology.” 2 Pakaluk also cites a passage indicating that <strong>Quine</strong> recognized<br />

the full force of Hume’s inductive skepticism: “The consequences<br />

[of Hume’s inductive skepticism are] that there is no rational<br />

basis for prediction, even probable prediction; no rational basis for<br />

scientific law, even probable law.” 3 As <strong>Quine</strong> understands Hume’s<br />

skeptical argument, it was intended to establish more than mere<br />

probabilism or fallibilism with respect to causal inferences – a reading,<br />

with <strong>Quine</strong>, I take to be correct.<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!