25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Quine</strong> and Logic 279<br />

to truth-functional logic than to the full-blown logic of quantification<br />

of which it is a precursor. The method is another illustration of<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s emphasis on efficiency of technique in an area’s coverage.<br />

Rules for the manipulation of quantifiers follow, together with<br />

reasons for them. Canons and examples of translation into the symbolic<br />

idiom are offered. There can be no complete method here, and<br />

students seem ever to want additional examples. In practice I have<br />

found it useful not only to proliferate illustrations of translation into<br />

logical notation, but also to emphasize translations from symbols<br />

back into English. Symbolic logic is a language, and students tend to<br />

need extensive drill to succeed in acquiring it.<br />

Since no formal system is afoot, there is no need to distinguish between<br />

what are usually contrasted as consistency, a syntactic property,<br />

and satisfiability. <strong>Quine</strong> uses the former term exclusively in<br />

Methods, but he gives it the semantic sense. To be consistent is<br />

to be sometimes true. Ultimately he shows that his principal proof<br />

procedure is both sound and complete, whence the distinction lapses<br />

anyway. What cannot be shown to generate contradiction is just what<br />

has a satisfying interpretation.<br />

That principal formal method for pure quantification theory is<br />

what <strong>Quine</strong> calls the main method, a variant of what is sometimes<br />

called semantic tableaux. It is one of several methods of the same<br />

strength included in the book. Three others, an extension of Skolem’s<br />

method of functional normal forms, a variant due to Dreben, and<br />

Herbrand’s method, are easily shown to be equal in power to the main<br />

method; the rest are somewhat further afield: a system of natural<br />

deduction for which <strong>Quine</strong> discusses strategies and two complete<br />

axiom systems outlined in passing. <strong>Quine</strong>’s stress continues to be<br />

on the method most efficient for the purpose at hand. The present<br />

purpose is cast as that of establishing joint inconsistency of finite<br />

collections of quantificational schemata.<br />

The main method is unsurpassed in both simplicity and applicability<br />

for this end. 5 First you need the notion of an instance of a<br />

quantification, of any schema with an initial quantifier that governs<br />

the whole schema. An instance is obtained when you drop that initial<br />

quantifier and supplant all the variable occurrences just freed by<br />

free occurrences of some one variable, called the instantial variable.<br />

I like to call it the pinch-hitting variable, though this has the peculiarity<br />

of allowing a variable – the one of the dropped quantifier – to<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!