25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Quine</strong> on Reference and Ontology 135<br />

Here, in the gap between the significance of the sentence and the significance<br />

of its parts, <strong>Quine</strong> sees empirical slack, which is manifest<br />

in ontological relativity.<br />

We have already seen a clear example of the gap between the significance<br />

of the whole sentence and the significance of its constituent<br />

parts. In the case of observation sentences, we saw that, taken as<br />

wholes, they get their meaning simply from their relation to sensory<br />

stimulation. If we think of them in that way, as responses to stimulation,<br />

we have no reason to view them as making any ontological<br />

claims. It becomes possible to see them as making such claims only<br />

when we take them to be part of a more sophisticated theory, which<br />

includes the notion of identity, plurals, and so on. To repeat the point<br />

of §I, the relation between language and the world by which our language<br />

comes to have empirical meaning and empirical content is not<br />

a relation between names and objects but rather a relation between<br />

sentences and sensory stimulations.<br />

This idea is fundamental for all of <strong>Quine</strong>’s views about language,<br />

and it underlies ontological relativity. For the idea applies not only<br />

to observation sentences but also to all sentences – to language as a<br />

whole. It is most clearly seen in the case of an observation sentence.<br />

One’s propensity to accept or reject such a sentence depends only on<br />

one’s current sensory stimulations. Other sentences are responsive<br />

not only to current stimulations but also to the other beliefs that<br />

one has. If two scientists, say, agree about what they are now seeing<br />

but disagree about whether it is evidence for a given claim, this will<br />

surely be because of some other disagreements. The claim is thus<br />

answerable not only to what they are then observing but also to<br />

the other things about which they disagree. The empirical meaning<br />

of such a sentence is not exhausted by its links to stimulations;<br />

it also consists of its links to other sentences. These sentence-tosentence<br />

links, and the dependencies of meaning they set up, are far<br />

too complex and many-sided for us be able to reconstruct them in<br />

detail.<br />

Let us quote a passage from Word and Object on this point. <strong>Quine</strong><br />

is considering the inference that a chemist may make from seeing a<br />

greenish tint in a test tube to thinking that the substance contains<br />

copper. Such an inference – from the observation sentence ‘It’s greenish’,<br />

let’s say, to ‘There was copper in it’ – obviously draws on the<br />

general background knowledge that our chemist possesses. <strong>Quine</strong><br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!