25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

56 richard creath<br />

reductionism, of course, but also to inspire and legitimate the holistic<br />

countersuggestion of modest reductionism.<br />

In any case, it is unclear whether we are to suppose that Carnap<br />

was a modest reductionist in 1950. In fact, Carnap was some sort of<br />

holist as early as the 1930s, 4 and he used notions from the theory<br />

of meaning to identify the wholes that could be confirmed, to determine<br />

which observations would be germane to those wholes, and to<br />

specify the degree of support or the kind of revisions required. Analyticity,<br />

therefore, is highly relevant to Carnap’s holistic epistemology<br />

even if not to <strong>Quine</strong>’s. Sententialism, that is, modest reductionism,<br />

can be considered quite apart from the question of whether Carnap<br />

endorsed it, and that seems to be what the issues of §5 resolve to.<br />

Unfortunately, <strong>Quine</strong> did not show such a view to be a dogma of<br />

any kind. In fact, the countersuggestion, amplified in the final section,<br />

“Empiricism without the Dogmas,” is all we ever get. Surely,<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> could not have intended to indict modest reductionism on<br />

the grounds of its parentage; who of us and what form of empiricism<br />

would survive so stern a judge? Not only is there no explicit<br />

argument against a form of reductionism that someone might currently<br />

hold, there is no explicit argument for the countersuggestion<br />

either. We are left to conclude that the elegance and coherence of his<br />

positive views were intended by <strong>Quine</strong> to be the argument, both for<br />

those views and against modest reductionism.<br />

Unfortunately, even in amplified form those positive views are<br />

presented in such sketchy terms that it is difficult or impossible to<br />

assess their merit. Now sketchiness is not always a vice. Sometimes,<br />

especially in the early stages of a project, it is actually better to lay<br />

out the general structure of a view without filling in details that have<br />

not yet emerged. But the details must eventually be forthcoming. As<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> himself said of another example,<br />

Russell had talked of deriving the world from experience by logical construction,<br />

but his constructions were sketchy and slight. Carnap, in Der logische<br />

Aufbau der Welt (1928), set himself to the task in earnest....Ifthebook did<br />

not achieve its exalted purpose, it did achieve a great deal. It afforded for the<br />

first time an example of what a scientific philosopher might aspire to in the<br />

way of rigor and explicitness. 5<br />

It is fair to say that <strong>Quine</strong>’s own argument against the definability<br />

of physical concepts in experiential terminology was possible only<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!