25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Aspects of <strong>Quine</strong>’s Naturalized Epistemology 35<br />

a naturalistic standpoint is that <strong>Quine</strong> actually embraces indeterminacy<br />

of translation as a substantive doctrine of his own.<br />

A similar concern arises with respect to the doctrine perhaps most<br />

dear to <strong>Quine</strong>’s heart, which he variously calls ontological relativity,<br />

inscrutability of reference, and indeterminacy of reference. Since I<br />

am primarily interested in the broad question of the relationship between<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s views concerning ontology and his naturalistic commitments,<br />

I will sketch his position concerning ontology in broad<br />

strokes. In “On What There Is,” <strong>Quine</strong> asked, “What is there?” and<br />

gave a startlingly simple answer: “Everything” (WTI 1). <strong>Quine</strong>, of<br />

course, was not saying that everything that could exist does exist.<br />

He was offering the empty answer “There is what there is” as preface<br />

to raising a different question: “[How can we determine] what the<br />

ontological commitments of a theory are?”<br />

Roughly, when we talk about things, we seem to commit ourselves<br />

to the existence of those things we are talking about. The<br />

most transparent way of doing this is to make an explicit claim that<br />

something exists – for example, that condors still exist in coastal California.<br />

More formally, we can put this remark about condors this<br />

way: There is at least one x such that x is a condor and x is in coastal<br />

California. This phrasing makes it transparent that employing this<br />

sentence commits one to the existence of condors and of coastal California.<br />

To reveal the ontological commitments of sentences that do<br />

not speak explicitly of something existing, we try to find a way to<br />

translate them into a form that does. Thus, ‘Some condors are female’<br />

becomes ‘There exists an x such that x is a condor and x is a<br />

female’, thus showing that the original sentence involved a commitment<br />

to the existence of both condors and females. Reflections along<br />

these lines, developed, needless to say, with more rigor and subtlety,<br />

led <strong>Quine</strong> to formulate his criterion of ontological commitment as<br />

follows:<br />

To be assumed as an entity is, purely and simply, to be reckoned as the value<br />

of a variable. (WTI 13)<br />

It seems, however, that there is a more obvious – more direct –<br />

way of referring to something in the world and thereby getting committed<br />

to its existence: the use of a proper name. The standard way<br />

of talking about Nixon is to use his name, to wit, ‘Nixon’. Why not<br />

also take the use of proper names as indicators of ontological commitment?<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s answer is that doing so raises difficult problems<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!