25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

256 daniel isaacson<br />

mathematics, it seems remarkable that he was unaware in writing<br />

it that he had significantly shifted in his position regarding what, by<br />

the account I have developed here, is the central issue for empiricism<br />

(and which impelled the Vienna Circle to move from positivism to<br />

logical positivism). But this passage reads as if he was unaware that he<br />

had shifted his position until Gibson pointed it out to him. Also, if it<br />

is a new position, it seems strange not to identify the motivation for<br />

the shift by explaining why the earlier position had to be abandoned.<br />

But all he does is “rest with the later position.” On the other hand,<br />

perhaps he misspoke himself in this reply, and where he said ‘later<br />

position’ should have said ‘later formulation’ (i.e., stated that what<br />

he had written in the passage in question is a better way to express<br />

a long-held position).<br />

These two possibilities (that the new passage is just a better formulation<br />

of a long-held position vs. that it marks the radical abandonment<br />

of what seemed to be the point of real difference between<br />

himself and Carnap) are not dichotomous. There is also the possibility<br />

that the passage expresses a new position but one that is consonant<br />

with the main elements of <strong>Quine</strong>’s philosophy overall. But<br />

clearly this is not the place to embark on a detailed investigation<br />

into <strong>Quine</strong>’s account of mathematics. 35<br />

5. conclusion<br />

In considering the relation between <strong>Quine</strong> and logical positivism, we<br />

have naturally focused on the relation between <strong>Quine</strong> and Carnap.<br />

Insofar as <strong>Quine</strong> held that mathematics, when applied, has empirical<br />

content, there is a substantive philosophical difference between<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s and Carnap’s views, one that turns centrally on acceptance<br />

versus rejection of the analytic-synthetic distinction. <strong>Quine</strong>’s philosophy<br />

remains true to the spirit of positivism, going back to its early<br />

progenitors, especially Comte, and differs in this important way from<br />

that of Carnap and the logical positivists.<br />

If, as some of his late writings suggest, <strong>Quine</strong>’s position was ultimately<br />

that mathematics has no empirical content, the difference<br />

between him and Carnap becomes much less clear. If <strong>Quine</strong> was<br />

prepared to agree with Carnap (and all logical positivists) that mathematics<br />

lacks empirical content, then his use of holism was not<br />

clearly different from Carnap’s. The way may then be open to sustain<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!