25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

276 joseph s. ullian<br />

a special hypothesis for the purpose at hand. Typical theorems thus<br />

have their own comprehension premises, letting us see clearly just<br />

what is required for their proof. Even the existence of infinite sets<br />

needs hypothesization, since the battery of adopted axioms does not<br />

deliver it. <strong>Quine</strong> has called the book’s treatment “pedagogically my<br />

preferred approach to the subject,” identifying his “expository objectives:<br />

clarity, elegance, and congenial philosophical perspective” (RW<br />

645). The book’s explicitness lies at the other end of the spectrum<br />

from the usual presentation of second-order logic, with its covert<br />

assumptions of existence.<br />

The final third of Set Theory and Its Logic surveys and compares<br />

five set theories, all but MK of the theories mentioned together earlier.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> makes comparisons in terms of predicativity, safety, and<br />

strength; issues of relative consistency are treated masterfully.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> wrote some twenty books, six of which are treatises entirely<br />

devoted to symbolic logic and set theory and another of which<br />

is a collection of logic papers culled from his enormous output of<br />

technical articles. There are scores of innovations and insights: an<br />

ingenious inversion trick for defining ‘natural number’, a definition<br />

of ordered pair on which everything is one, a penetrating analysis of<br />

ω-consistency, reduction of logic’s basis to inclusion and abstraction,<br />

a host of proof procedures, and a rendering of Gödel’s Incompleteness<br />

Theorem by way of concatenation theory. This only scratches the<br />

surface. <strong>Quine</strong>’s contribution to the field is not to be measured in<br />

terms of proved theorems, proposed theories, or striking simplifications,<br />

however many there were of each. Much of what he taught us<br />

has come to be taken for granted, as he has been one of the dominant<br />

influences on students of logic for more than half a century. He<br />

helped to shape the field of mathematical logic as much as anyone.<br />

He showed us patiently and caringly how to see the subject, how to<br />

express ourselves in it, and how to connect it with the rest of what<br />

we would know.<br />

II<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> wrote that “the pedagogical motive has dominated my work<br />

in logic” (RW 644). He had found no suitable text for teaching formal<br />

logic in 1936, when he began his instructorship at Harvard. This<br />

started him on a “project...ofpedagogical engineering” that led first<br />

to his Elementary Logic (1941) and subsequently to the four editions<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!