25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Aspects of <strong>Quine</strong>’s Naturalized Epistemology 29<br />

external world and its history. The relation between the meager input and<br />

torrential output is a relation that we are prompted to study for somewhat<br />

the same reasons that always prompted epistemology; namely, in order to<br />

see how evidence relates to theory....(EN82–3)<br />

Passages of this sort suggest that <strong>Quine</strong> might be interested in going<br />

behind sensory surfaces in order to understand the “inner loop”<br />

of brain structures that link hits on sensory surfaces with linguistic<br />

expressions emitted, for example, by mouths. That would be<br />

epistemology naturalized with a vengeance. But despite his general<br />

commitment to physicalism, <strong>Quine</strong> does not opt for physiological<br />

psychology as his methodological standpoint. His writings contain<br />

no serious considerations of such things as “assorted frequencies,”<br />

rods and cones, brain regions, or articulatory mechanisms. Instead,<br />

he adopts a behaviorist approach that explores the “outer loop” between<br />

publicly observable stimulatory situations and the publicly<br />

observable linguistic utterances that occur in such situations. The<br />

structures under consideration are not brain structures but sociolinguistic<br />

structures. As a product of his century, <strong>Quine</strong> replaces the<br />

way of ideas with the way of words; the way of things, though officially<br />

endorsed, is enshrined as a far-off ideal.<br />

Just as a naturalized epistemology can take various forms depending<br />

on the empirical disciplines on which it relies, a naturalized empiricism<br />

can itself be developed in a variety of ways. Put perhaps too<br />

simply, <strong>Quine</strong>’s version of naturalized empiricism, though deeply<br />

indebted to Hume, arose primarily from his critical reflections on<br />

the work of the logical empiricists, most notably Rudolph Carnap.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s most famous assault on logical empiricism is found in his<br />

essay “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” Despite what the title may<br />

seem to suggest, the aim of this essay is not to reject empiricism but<br />

instead to argue that the logical empiricists were not themselves sufficiently<br />

empirical in their outlook. Though it would scan less well,<br />

“Two Dogmas of Empiricism” would have been more accurately titled<br />

“Two Nonempiricist Dogmas Surviving in Logical Empiricism.”<br />

Broadly speaking, what <strong>Quine</strong> rejected as being antiempirical were<br />

the a priori conceptual methods embodied in the use of the analyticsynthetic<br />

distinction and, as noted earlier, the attempt to give reductive<br />

(or even quasi-reductive) analyses of empirical concepts. <strong>Quine</strong>,<br />

we might say, rejected the lingering apriorism of logical empiricism.<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!