25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Quine</strong> and Logical Positivism 239<br />

known not on an ultimate basis of sensory experience, in particular<br />

mathematics and logic, is analytic. The result of Carnap’s investigations<br />

was The Logical Syntax of Language. This second attempt to<br />

establish a logical positivism – that is, to use logic to uphold a modified<br />

form of positivism – had been necessitated by the realization<br />

that key axioms of Principia Mathematica could not be defended as<br />

logically true (see Carnap 1931) and by the impact of Gödel’s incompleteness<br />

theorems. Carnap’s solution was to employ a conventionalist<br />

notion of logic and analyticity, relativized to the choice of language<br />

according to his principle of logical tolerance, and it was also<br />

dependent on using a broader notion of logical consequence, going<br />

beyond formal deduction, to overcome the limitations on deductive<br />

systems revealed by the incompleteness theorems.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> was greatly taken by this means of upholding empiricism,<br />

though he soon had misgivings, which focused on the issue of<br />

whether the distinction between analytic and synthetic, on which it<br />

depended, could itself be drawn on an empiricist basis. It is a striking<br />

fact that for all <strong>Quine</strong>’s initial enthusiasm for The Logical Syntax of<br />

Language, he never published anything about it that he later had occasion<br />

to retract. Thus the Harvard lectures, which expounded and<br />

endorsed logical syntax, were never published (by him), and his review<br />

of The Logical Syntax of Language, which he published in 1935,<br />

did not endorse those key claims of Carnap’s. Here is a sentence from<br />

the first of the three lectures on Carnap: “All such sentences, in<br />

other words all mathematics and logic, become analytic: direct consequences<br />

of our definitions, or conventions as to the use of words”<br />

(Creath 1990, 60). And consider this ringing declaration of faith in<br />

the analytic-synthetic distinction:<br />

When we adopt such a syntax, in which the a priori is confined to the analytic,<br />

every true proposition then falls into one of two classes: either it is<br />

a synthetic empirical proposition, belonging within one or another of the<br />

natural sciences, or it is an a priori analytic proposition, in which case it<br />

derives its validity from the conventional structure, or syntax, of the language<br />

itself – “syntax” being broadly enough construed to cover all linguistic<br />

conventions. (p. 66)<br />

This passage leads immediately to an endorsement of Carnap’s conception<br />

of philosophy as separate from science, another point <strong>Quine</strong><br />

would later repudiate:<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!