25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

248 daniel isaacson<br />

of <strong>Quine</strong>’s philosophy of mathematics would show in any case that<br />

the analytic-synthetic distinction was unnecessary for empiricism,<br />

thereby leaving those who would defend it with little to be gained<br />

from doing so.<br />

For Carnap, mathematics was the fundamental issue for his attempt<br />

to uphold empiricism. <strong>Quine</strong> saw that this was so:<br />

I think Carnap’s tenacity to analyticity was due largely to his philosophy of<br />

mathematics. One problem for him was the lack of empirical content: how<br />

could an empiricist accept mathematics as meaningful? Another problem<br />

was the necessity of mathematical truth. Analyticity was his answer to<br />

both. (TDR 269)<br />

The case of mathematics was not central to <strong>Quine</strong>’s formulation<br />

of empiricism, but he held that his empiricism could account for<br />

mathematics, as of course he realized it must. He followed the preceding<br />

characterization of Carnap’s philosophy with this account of<br />

his own:<br />

I answer both with my moderate holism. Take the first problem: lack of<br />

content. Insofar as mathematics gets applied in natural sciences, I see it<br />

as sharing empirical content. Sentences of pure arithmetic and differential<br />

calculus contribute indispensably to the critical semantic mass of various<br />

clusters of scientific hypotheses, and so partake of the empirical content<br />

imbibed from the implied observation categoricals....<br />

What then about the other problem, that of the necessity of mathematical<br />

truth? This again is nicely cleared up by moderate holism, without the help<br />

of analyticity. For let us recall that when a cluster of sentences with critical<br />

semantic mass is refuted by an experiment, the crisis can be resolved<br />

by revoking one or another sentence of the cluster. We hope to choose in<br />

such a way as to optimize future progress. If one of the sentences is purely<br />

mathematical, we will not choose to revoke it; such a move would reverberate<br />

excessively through the rest of science. We are restrained by a maxim<br />

of minimum multilation. It is simply in this, I hold, that the necessity of<br />

mathematics lies: our determination to make revisions elsewhere instead. I<br />

make no deeper sense of necessity anywhere. (TDR 269–70)<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s philosophy of mathematics has to be gleaned from scattered<br />

remarks, such as those just quoted. No section, let alone chapter,<br />

of Word and Object is devoted to mathematics, and indeed there<br />

is no entry for mathematics in the index of this most central text for<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s philosophy. No one of <strong>Quine</strong>’s myriad papers is devoted to<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!