25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Quine</strong> on Reference and Ontology 137<br />

the sentence as made up of parts that are themselves significant. The<br />

qualification is that it will in fact be impossible for us to use theoretical<br />

sentences correctly without an analysis of those sentences<br />

into significant constituent parts. Take the most obvious case, that<br />

of the “so-called logical connections” between sentences. A logical<br />

connection may be thought of as summing up infinitely many facts<br />

of the following form: Whenever it is appropriate to assert that sentence,<br />

it is also appropriate to assert this one. But we could not learn<br />

all of these facts one by one. What we learn – implicitly at first, explicitly<br />

from logic books – is that whenever it is appropriate to assert<br />

a sentence of this form, it is appropriate also to assert a corresponding<br />

sentence of that form. But this requires that we attribute forms<br />

to sentences, that is, see them as made up of constituent parts and<br />

patterns that are significant and recur in other sentences.<br />

Let us see where we are in our argument. Reference is a relation<br />

between words – significant constituent parts of sentences – and<br />

objects. The fundamental relation of language to the world, the relation<br />

that guarantees empirical significance to our language, however,<br />

does not take place at that level but rather at the level of the relation<br />

between sentences and stimulations. We are bound to attribute<br />

significance to constituent parts of sentences because it is only in<br />

that way that we can see the patterns and analogies in language that<br />

make it possible for us to use it. This situation leaves it open that<br />

there might in fact be more than one way to attribute structure to<br />

our sentences, more than one way to attribute significance to their<br />

constituent parts – more than one way to analyze them so as to<br />

make perspicuous sense of our language. And note that if there were,<br />

then there would be no way to bring evidence to bear on the question<br />

which of the methods of analysis is correct. Evidence, as <strong>Quine</strong><br />

conceives it, bears on whole sentences, and the imagined dispute<br />

is between two ways of breaking sentences down into constituent<br />

parts, ways that will make no difference to which sentences are to<br />

be accepted.<br />

Here we have, in outline, <strong>Quine</strong>’s doctrine of ontological relativity,<br />

or at least the necessary background to that doctrine. Let us see<br />

how <strong>Quine</strong> encapsulates some of the points we have been making:<br />

Reference and ontology recede thus to the status of mere auxiliaries. True<br />

sentences, observational and theoretical, are the alpha and omega of the<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!