25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

216 daniel isaacson<br />

For <strong>Quine</strong>, such indeterminacy appears to be “inescapable” when<br />

“we take a verification theory of meaning seriously” (EN 80). <strong>Quine</strong><br />

recognizes that this doctrine of indeterminacy upsets our preconceptions<br />

about language:<br />

Should the unwelcomeness of the conclusion persuade us to abandon the<br />

verification theory of meaning? Certainly not. The sort of meaning that is<br />

basic to translation, and to the learning of one’s own language, is necessarily<br />

empirical meaning and nothing more. 4 (EN 81)<br />

It seems natural, then, despite <strong>Quine</strong>’s rejection of what were central<br />

doctrines of logical positivism in the 1930s, to see him as working<br />

within rather than against the empiricist project of logical positivism.<br />

A. J. Ayer (1959), in the introduction to his anthology Logical<br />

Positivism, declared,<br />

In the United States a number of philosophers like <strong>Quine</strong>, Nagel and Nelson<br />

Goodman conduct logical analysis in a systematic scientific spirit that is<br />

probably closer to the original ideal of the Vienna Circle than anything that<br />

is now to be met with elsewhere. (pp. 7–8)<br />

And <strong>Quine</strong>’s long-time colleague Hilary Putnam (1990) hailed <strong>Quine</strong><br />

as “The Greatest Logical Positivist” (in an article for which this<br />

accolade served as title):<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> is often thought to have destroyed logical positivism, with his rejection<br />

of the analytic-synthetic distinction and his likening of philosophy to<br />

natural science rather than to pure logic, and indeed, a generation of young<br />

“scientific realist” philosophers has been inspired by him to denounce logical<br />

positivism root and branch. But reading these essays, I must say that I<br />

am inclined to class <strong>Quine</strong> as the last and greatest of the logical positivists,<br />

in spite of his criticisms of the movement. (p. 269)<br />

These views of the relation between <strong>Quine</strong> and logical positivism<br />

are in keeping with a characteristic of logical positivism itself,<br />

namely, that its adherents held no single doctrine sacrosanct. Joergen<br />

Joergensen (1951), a Scandinavian associate of the Vienna Circle,<br />

writing its history, declared that “what unites its members is...not<br />

so much definite views or dogmas as definite tendencies and endeavors.<br />

An evidence of this is the often considerable divergence and<br />

lively discussion between its members and the amendments in the<br />

fundamental views that have occurred several times in the course<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!