25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

52 richard creath<br />

the theory of meaning – for example, ‘analyticity’, ‘synonymy’, ‘intension’,<br />

and ‘meaning’ – are fully interdefinable. Thus, behavioral<br />

criteria for synonymy, say, would suffice for all the rest.<br />

It is important to note that the issue with behavioral criteria is<br />

intelligibility, not truth. This is what makes the <strong>Quine</strong>an response<br />

to the proposal gambit extremely powerful. So construed, however,<br />

it cannot be further demanded, if and when behavioral criteria are<br />

provided, that they must also turn Carnap’s claims as to what is<br />

or is not analytic into a true theory of English. (Note: And so it is<br />

with geometry as well. Correspondence rules [observational criteria]<br />

were needed to make the axioms deserve the name ‘geometry’ at all.<br />

There can be no further requirement that they turn, say, Euclidian<br />

geometry into a true description of physical space.) Carnap says that<br />

logic and mathematics are to be counted among the analytic truths<br />

and that quantum mechanics, taken as a whole, is not. This need<br />

not be taken as a claim about English, and Carnap himself is explicit<br />

that what he says is to be taken as a proposal. Granted, Carnap undoubtedly<br />

thought that logic and mathematics were in fact analytic<br />

in English. But it is irrelevant to the merits of Carnap’s proposal as<br />

a proposal whether English already embodies it. Now it would be<br />

a serious objection to a set of criteria if nothing or everything always<br />

turned out to be analytic under the criteria. More specifically,<br />

it would be equally objectionable if there were no possible language<br />

in which logic and mathematics turn out to be analytic while quantum<br />

mechanics and the general theory of relativity (taken as wholes)<br />

turn out to be synthetic. These objections would be grave, but they<br />

would also be very difficult objections to sustain, even if one wanted<br />

to talk about all possible languages, which <strong>Quine</strong> certainly does<br />

not.<br />

Moreover, <strong>Quine</strong> attempts no direct argument that suitable behavioral<br />

criteria cannot be provided. Instead, what he does in “Two<br />

Dogmas” is to survey various attempts to clarify the theory of meaning.<br />

Does <strong>Quine</strong> look in all the right places? For the most part, yes,<br />

but given the conspicuously epistemic role of analyticity (it was,<br />

after all, a replacement for the apriority), the best place to look for<br />

meanings for a natural language ought to be in the community’s epistemic<br />

activity. Thus, when the issue is translation, what the natives<br />

say about rabbits should matter less than what they say, in justification<br />

or criticism, about what they say. The questions to ask include<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!