25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Quine</strong> on Reference and Ontology 147<br />

to speculate on the nature of reification and its utility for scientific<br />

theory” (PTb 8, emphasis added).<br />

8. See WO 93. In a striking image, <strong>Quine</strong> there compares such acquisition<br />

to a climbers ascent of a “chimney,” or narrow space between two<br />

rock faces: “The contextual learning of these various particles goes on<br />

simultaneously, we may suppose, so that they are gradually adjusted to<br />

one another and a coherent pattern of usage is evolved matching that<br />

of society. The child scrambles up an intellectual chimney, supporting<br />

himself against each side by pressure against the others.”<br />

9. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M.<br />

Anscombe (New York: Macmillan, 1953), §257.<br />

10. Very roughly, first-order quantification theory is a logic that enables us<br />

to generalize over all objects – and hence to speak of all objects being<br />

thus-and-so, or no objects, or at least one object. <strong>Quine</strong> generally takes<br />

logic to include the notion of identity and rules governing its use (see<br />

PL, chap. 6). By contrast with first-order logic, second-order logic would<br />

add the capacity to generalize about properties or qualities of objects.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> does not favor second-order logic, both because its truths cannot<br />

be captured by any precisely formulated system of axioms or rules and<br />

because he finds the idea of a property or quality to be unclear. He<br />

holds that it is both philosophically less misleading and technically<br />

more advantageous to use instead a combination of first-order logic and<br />

set theory.<br />

11. Thus <strong>Quine</strong> speaks of the “triviality” of the connection between ontology<br />

and quantification, saying that the connection “is trivially assured<br />

by the very explanation of referential quantification” (see RFK 174–5).<br />

By “referential quantification,” <strong>Quine</strong> here means the sort of qualification<br />

just explained, which he, along with most logicians, generally takes<br />

as standard. It is opposed to “substitutional quantification,” in which<br />

we think not of open sentences being true of this or that object but<br />

rather as yielding truths when a given name replaces the variable. The<br />

difference shows up if we admit objects not all of which have names;<br />

in the case of real numbers, we cannot avoid doing so, since there are<br />

more of them than there can be names.<br />

12. <strong>Quine</strong> is perhaps influenced here by his early work in set theory, where<br />

the question of the entities in the range of the quantifiers of a given theory<br />

is a very natural measure of the strength of that theory and where the<br />

strength of the theory is in turn crucial to its vulnerability to paradox.<br />

I am indebted here to Stephen Menn.<br />

13. The theory is first set forth in Russell’s “On Denoting” (Mind 14 [1905]:<br />

479–93; very widely reprinted) but is perhaps to be seen more clearly in<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!