25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

30 robert j. fogelin<br />

Yet even if he attacked logical empiricism in fundamental ways, he<br />

still accepted (or fell in with) some of its most important features.<br />

The underlying shared thought is that empirical science is a linguistic<br />

structure. Thus for <strong>Quine</strong>, as for the logical empiricists, the<br />

philosophy of empirical science is the study of the language of empirical<br />

science. Not only does this assumption underlie <strong>Quine</strong>’s practice<br />

in dealing with empirical science, it is also a doctrine that he states<br />

explicitly in a number of places. For example, in “The Nature of Natural<br />

Knowledge,” <strong>Quine</strong> remarks, “Science is a ponderous linguistic<br />

structure, fabricated of theoretical terms linked by fabricated hypotheses,<br />

and keyed to observable events here and there” (NNK 71).<br />

The central point of this passage is that science is, except for its observational<br />

content, a human fabrication. We will return to this point<br />

shortly. It is, however, worth pausing over the claim that science is<br />

a linguistic structure. This seems to be stronger than the claim that<br />

science employs linguistic structures. Bowling, for example, employs<br />

linguistic structures – score sheets – yet no one would say that bowling<br />

is a linguistic structure. In saying that science is a linguistic<br />

structure, <strong>Quine</strong> seems to be identifying science with its theories.<br />

Treating science (or a scientific theory) as a linguistic structure is<br />

common ground between <strong>Quine</strong> and the logical empiricists. Among<br />

other things, this explains why the methods of logic are important<br />

to both and why <strong>Quine</strong>’s constructive work often shadows Carnap’s.<br />

Their differences have already been spelled out. For <strong>Quine</strong>, a naturalized<br />

empiricism was made possible by a set of interlocking considerations.<br />

By abandoning the project of validating science, <strong>Quine</strong><br />

evades the charge of circularity. By rejecting the analytic-synthetic<br />

distinction, he undercuts the purely conceptual programs it made<br />

possible. By arguing for a wide range of indeterminacies, he deprives<br />

the logical empiricists of their chief employment: the production of<br />

reductive analyses. For <strong>Quine</strong>, these changes yield a form of empiricism<br />

more empirical than logical empiricism itself.<br />

In summary, depending on the context, <strong>Quine</strong>’s naturalism with<br />

respect to epistemology operates on at least three levels:<br />

� Naturalized epistemology. This is broad view that epistemological<br />

questions are factual questions to be addressed using<br />

the results and methods of empirical science.<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!