25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

274 joseph s. ullian<br />

the predicative proposals of Weyl and Wang, he speaks of himself<br />

as “never tempted to embrace constructivism at the cost of trading<br />

our crystalline bivalent logic for the fog of intuitionism” (RW 648).<br />

Of intuitionism he has also written that it muddies “the distinction<br />

between saying a sentence and talking about it” and that it “lacks<br />

the familiarity, the convenience, the simplicity, and the beauty of<br />

our logic” (PL 87).<br />

What has caught <strong>Quine</strong>’s eye with less disfavor is the intriguing<br />

mechanism of branching quantifiers. Is their exclusion from our logic<br />

an arbitrary matter? In “Existence and Quantification” (p.109), he<br />

attributes to Henkin consideration of sentences like this one:<br />

Each thing bears P to something y and each thing bears<br />

(1)<br />

Q to something w such that Ryw.<br />

It turns out that the two symmetric ways of rendering this in standard<br />

quantificational form are not equivalent to each other, nor is either<br />

equivalent to the natural construal of the branched<br />

(2)<br />

∀x ∃y<br />

∀z∃w (Pxy.Qzw.Ryw),<br />

a form recommended by Henkin to make (1)’s intended dependencies<br />

explicit. 3<br />

It has been debated whether English has sentences that are best<br />

cast in terms of branching quantifiers. Barwise analyzed a broad array<br />

of candidates and explored semantics for them. 4 One was Hintikka’s<br />

favorite example: “Some relative of each villager and some relative<br />

of each townsman hate each other.” Perhaps more seductive was<br />

Gabbay and Moravcsik’s “Every man loves some woman (and) every<br />

sheep befriends some girl that belong to the same club.” Barwise<br />

concluded that “branching quantification does occur naturally in<br />

English.”<br />

Henkin noted that there is a more conventional way of setting<br />

down a sentence like (1). It would be the conspicuously second-order<br />

(3) ∃ f ∃g ∀x ∀z(Pxfx.Qzgz.Rfxgz).<br />

This sentence quantifies over functions; (2) did not but departed from<br />

the standard use of quantifiers. Might there be sufficient reason to<br />

extend logic to include such branched schemata as (2) or even such<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!