25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Quine</strong> on Reference and Ontology 143<br />

theory of the world. The lesson of inscrutability, by contrast, is that<br />

there is no more to an object than its role in theory. 31<br />

V<br />

Finally, I want to raise, and very briefly to address, a difficult question<br />

on which <strong>Quine</strong>’s own writings give us comparatively little guidance.<br />

To what extent does the relativity of ontology, as we discussed<br />

it in the previous section, undermine the importance that <strong>Quine</strong><br />

attributed to ontology and to reference, at least in earlier decades?<br />

There was certainly a shift of emphasis in his work as he came to formulate<br />

the inscrutability of reference and then to lay greater stress<br />

on it. The present question is whether this was merely a shift of<br />

emphasis or did it also have repercussions on the central <strong>Quine</strong>an<br />

tenets relating to reference?<br />

For <strong>Quine</strong>, as we saw in §II, studying the referential structure of<br />

our language is a central way of gaining insight into its functioning;<br />

clarifying that structure – replacing it with a better – is a central<br />

way in which we may clarify and improve our language and our<br />

conceptual scheme. These ideas seem to me quite untouched by an<br />

acceptance of ontological relativity. The insight into our language<br />

that studies of reference afford is precisely an insight into its referential<br />

structure, and this is not affected by ontological relativity.<br />

That idea suggests that it is indifferent whether we take ourselves<br />

to be referring to one set of objects or to another set of objects that<br />

play the exact same roles in our theory. And it is the roles that are<br />

at stake in <strong>Quine</strong>an studies of reference.<br />

When <strong>Quine</strong> suggests ontological reform, the sort of clarification<br />

he offers also survives, I think, an appreciation of ontological relativity.<br />

Thus he offers a definition of ordered pairs, for example, and a<br />

way of reconstruing talk of states of mind as talk of states of body. 32<br />

The ontological reforms <strong>Quine</strong> favors can perfectly well be understood<br />

in terms of an object’s theoretical role (i.e., its place in the<br />

structure of our theory). Let us consider minds and bodies. <strong>Quine</strong>’s<br />

reasons for not wanting to take talk of states of mind at face value,<br />

such as their lack of clear identity criteria, will apply equally to anything<br />

playing the same theoretical role – that is, to any proxy for<br />

states of mind. And by the same token, any proxy for states of body<br />

will have the advantages that lead <strong>Quine</strong> to prefer them to states of<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!