25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

130 peter hylton<br />

Now what has this to do with ontology? The answer is that, on<br />

this view, ontology becomes language-relative. Ontology will vary<br />

from language to language: This language might take sets as basic and<br />

define expressions for numbers, whereas this other language might<br />

have no set theory and presuppose the existence of the numbers outright.<br />

More drastically, we might choose to speak a language of sensedata<br />

– one in which the basic terms refer to immediate experience –<br />

rather than the language of physical objects that we in fact speak.<br />

So an ontological question, say, ‘Are there sets?’ has no flat-out answer.<br />

The proper initial response is, it depends on what language you<br />

choose to speak. Independent of the choice of language, there simply<br />

is no answer to the question – indeed, Carnap holds that if we<br />

attempt to ask the question absolutely rather than relative to some<br />

particular language, then we are crossing the bounds of sense: There<br />

simply is no absolute question to be asked.<br />

The result of this is that the ontological question vanishes, along<br />

with other metaphysical questions. The ontological question was<br />

precisely the absolute question, and Carnap denies it any meaning.<br />

Thus we may, on Carnap’s account, speak a language that quantifies<br />

over sets, say. But this does not commit us to saying that there really<br />

are sets, in some language-independent sense. There is no languageindependent<br />

sense in which we can say what there is or isn’t. Of<br />

course, while we are speaking that language, we will assert that<br />

there are sets (or at least that sets of this or that kind exist). But<br />

our speaking that language implies nothing more than that for certain<br />

purposes we find it convenient and useful; our saying things in<br />

it implies only that given the language those sentences are correct.<br />

For Carnap, there really is no ontological commitment at all.<br />

This defusing of ontology depends on the idea that the adoption<br />

of a language is, in principle at least, separable from the adoption of<br />

a theory within a language. Carnap’s position here requires that the<br />

two have different epistemological bases: Within a language there<br />

are rules that determine which theory is correct; the lack of corresponding<br />

rules governing choice of language makes it, by contrast, a<br />

fit area for tolerance.<br />

This nexus of ideas is equivalent to an epistemologically significant<br />

distinction between the analytic and the synthetic. If we<br />

could clearly distinguish changes of language from changes of theory<br />

within a language, then we could clearly distinguish analytic<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!