25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

280 joseph s. ullian<br />

pinch-hit for itself. The result of just dropping that outermost quantifier<br />

will always pass muster as an instance.<br />

Now the main method: Transform each of the schemata whose<br />

joint inconsistency is sought into prenex form, and do so in such a<br />

way that no variable free in one of them is quantified in another (thus<br />

forestalling interference with needed instantiations). Then take instances<br />

of schemata that you have and that you generate, subject<br />

only to one vital restriction. When you take an instance of an existential<br />

quantification, the pinch-hitting variable must not be free in<br />

any earlier line; for short, it must be new. So no moving from ‘∃xFx’<br />

and ‘∃x − Fx’ to‘Fy’ and ‘−Fy’, for this requires ‘y’ to be new at two<br />

different junctures. A good thing, too, in light of the compatibility<br />

of the two quantifications. That is all you do, generate instances<br />

in accord with the restriction (which does not limit instantiations<br />

of universal quantifications). When and only when you assemble a<br />

truth-functionally inconsistent collection of unquantified lines have<br />

you succeeded in proving joint inconsistency of the original batch.<br />

And of course whether such a truth-functionally inconsistent set<br />

(call it a tfi combo) has been assembled is routinely checkable by any<br />

method suitable for testing truth-functional consistency. Thus the<br />

main method reduces inconsistency of quantificational schemata to<br />

something that can be verified.<br />

But their consistency is not thereby so reduced, since for the initial<br />

batch to be consistent is for no tfi combo ever to accrue. In general,<br />

it cannot be inferred that because none has surfaced so far none can<br />

be obtained. Proofs of inconsistency, even for short schemata, can<br />

run as long as you wish. So the main method, though shown to be<br />

complete (adequate to proving inconsistency wherever it lurks), is<br />

no decision procedure, no algorithm always emitting a right answer.<br />

From Church, of course, we know that no such algorithm exists.<br />

Since validity is just inconsistency of the negation, any complete<br />

method for showing inconsistency of quantificational schemata confers<br />

on us a complete method for establishing validity as well, but<br />

still without hope of an algorithm for the purpose. Given a quantificational<br />

schema we know that a complete proof procedure will<br />

allow verification of its validity if it is valid, yet will in general reveal<br />

nothing if it fails of validity.<br />

Keeping our focus on validity, there are some natural subclasses<br />

of the quantificational schemata that do have validity tests. As<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!