25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Quine</strong> and Logic 277<br />

of Methods of Logic (1950, 1959, 1972, and 1982), each after the first<br />

a considerable enlargement of the one before it. I have used all four<br />

editions of the text in what seem myriad offerings of my class in<br />

basic symbolic logic. I first learned the subject from <strong>Quine</strong>, studying<br />

its mimeographed predecessor.<br />

Methods of Logic is like no other text in the subject. First of all,<br />

it is very appropriately titled. It serves up a veritable feast of methods,<br />

thoughtfully prepared for application and well garnished with<br />

their rationales. The book encompasses all that <strong>Quine</strong> sees as falling<br />

within logic’s realm, and indeed somewhat more. Methods builds on<br />

no abstract system with formal rules. In it <strong>Quine</strong> gives us machinery<br />

ready to use and not bogged down in technicalities that serve no<br />

practical purpose. Still, the book is crisp, precise, and painstaking,<br />

imparting regard for rigorous thinking at every turn.<br />

Early we find <strong>Quine</strong> shunning the distinction between a sentence<br />

letter and its double negation. Since this is classical logic, the two<br />

will cash out in the same way (although in chap. 13’s axiom system,<br />

a brief departure, they need to be distinguished). Similarly, it<br />

is efficient to take both conjunction and alternation (<strong>Quine</strong> favors<br />

‘alternation’ over ‘disjunction’) as capable of combining any finite<br />

plurality of components, not just two. <strong>Quine</strong> is eschewing fussiness<br />

that would slow application of the mechanism.<br />

Since the symbolic expressions that are the heart of the subject<br />

are not part of a formal system, <strong>Quine</strong> does not call them formulas.<br />

He emphasizes that what they do is schematically represent the sentences<br />

that realize them; they serve as “logical diagrams,” and he<br />

calls them schemata. Thus ‘pvqvr’ is a schema, representing any<br />

threefold alternation. A schema is fleshed out by taking actual<br />

sentences, and later predicates, to supplant its schematic letters. We<br />

think of the letters as proxies. <strong>Quine</strong>’s schemata are ready to use.<br />

They are symbolizations that might be given to the sentences, however<br />

complex, that they represent.<br />

That view of logic’s symbolic expressions lays bare what is always<br />

implicit in the subject’s development: The logical truths are<br />

just those that realize valid schemata, or, turned around more usefully,<br />

a sentence is a logical truth just in case it has some correct<br />

symbolization that is valid.<br />

For testing validity or consistency of truth-functional schemata,<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> favors his method of truth-value analysis. In addition to giving<br />

all the information of truth tables, this technique allows us to<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!