25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

134 peter hylton<br />

best theory of the world to be real, in the only sense that word has.<br />

In another sense, it is not metaphysical, for it is not to be settled<br />

by anything resembling a priori speculation. It is settled, rather, by<br />

the ordinary processes by which our theories of the world are constructed.<br />

For <strong>Quine</strong>, his own reflections on ontological commitment<br />

and his use of regimentation and of reduction (e.g., of ordered pairs<br />

to sets) are part of that process of theory construction – the part that<br />

is particularly concerned with the clarity of the theory and with the<br />

avoidance of useless questions.<br />

<strong>Quine</strong> is thus a realist about ontology, not a relativist, at least not<br />

in the way in which Carnap was. Carnap’s relativism was a relativism<br />

of language based on the principle of tolerance; <strong>Quine</strong>’s rejection of an<br />

epistemologically grounded distinction between the analytic and the<br />

synthetic undermines that principle entirely. This is not to say that<br />

for <strong>Quine</strong> questions of ontology have nothing to do with language.<br />

On the contrary, many ontological questions can be conveniently<br />

phrased as questions about language, such as the choice between the<br />

language of Newtonian mechanics and the language of relativistic<br />

mechanics. The contrast with Carnap is that for <strong>Quine</strong> there is a<br />

correct answer to the question of language choice. If one theory enables<br />

us to predict and deal with events better than another, then the<br />

language of the first is the one we should accept. And in accepting it,<br />

we no doubt accept a certain range of entities as existing – we accept<br />

an ontology.<br />

IV<br />

In one way, then, <strong>Quine</strong> is not a relativist about ontology; in another<br />

way, however, he is. Indeed, the <strong>Quine</strong>an doctrine known as<br />

ontological relativity or the inscrutability of reference has become<br />

famous, even notorious. This form of relativism about ontology is<br />

not derivative from relativism about truth: On the contrary, it occurs<br />

even if we suppose all problems about truth to be settled – even if<br />

we suppose that we possess a theory of the world whose complete<br />

truth is not in doubt. Such a completely true theory is, after all, a<br />

body of true sentences. The referential burden of language, however,<br />

is not simply a matter of which sentences are true but also a matter<br />

of how we see those sentences as making ontological claims. It is<br />

thus a matter of how the whole sentences are analyzed into parts.<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!