25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

132 peter hylton<br />

are made and justified on what is, seen very abstractly, the same sort<br />

of basis. Even if we can distinguish changes of language from changes<br />

of theory within a language, there is no reason to say that we have a<br />

notion of correctness for changes of the one kind but not for changes<br />

of the other. Changes of language would, at least in principle, be as<br />

much matters of correctness as changes of theory within a language,<br />

for all changes would be justified by appeal to the overarching aim<br />

of achieving a simple and empirically correct theory of the world.<br />

Hence there is no reason to invoke the principle of tolerance.<br />

The rejection of the principle of tolerance makes all the difference<br />

to the status of ontology. For Carnap, the question whether we should<br />

use Newtonian or relativistic mechanics was a question of choice of<br />

language and therefore a matter for free choice rather than a rightor-wrong<br />

issue. For <strong>Quine</strong>, it is also perhaps largely a question of<br />

language but not therefore a matter for free choice. The language<br />

of relativistic mechanics makes possible a preferable theory and is<br />

therefore a better choice. Language relativity, after all, does not arise<br />

merely from the existence of a multiplicity of distinct languages,<br />

any more than the (supposed) relativity of ethics arises merely from<br />

the existence of a multiplicity of opinions on that subject. What is<br />

required is, in addition, the idea that there is no basis for choosing<br />

one as better than another and that therefore a relativized answer is<br />

the best we can achieve. In rejecting the principle of tolerance, <strong>Quine</strong><br />

rejects just this sort of relativism about language choice.<br />

The upshot of this is a general rejection of Carnap’s relativism,<br />

most clearly seen, perhaps, in the case of truth. We no longer say, with<br />

Carnap, that so-and-so is true relative to the choice of such-and-such<br />

language. It is because of his doubts about the distinction between<br />

language and beliefs accepted within a language that <strong>Quine</strong> generally<br />

speaks simply of “theory,” meaning all the sentences that we accept.<br />

He recognizes, of course, that various theories are possible, but he<br />

denies that this makes for relativity. If a sentence is part of the theory<br />

that we hold, then we accept that sentence as true – not true in some<br />

relativized sense but flat-out. (This does not show, of course, that<br />

we will not later change our minds. Nothing, in <strong>Quine</strong>’s view, can<br />

rule this out; he is a fallibilist through and through.) That is simply<br />

what it is to hold a theory, and since we cannot get by without some<br />

theory or other to guide us through the world, we must hold the<br />

best we can. Having said that we can only make sense of the idea<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!